1 decisions under risk: probability 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 :...

174
1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指指指指 : 指指指 指指 指指指 : 指指指 指 指 : 2009 指 10 指 26 指

Upload: kendal-sell

Post on 01-Apr-2015

275 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

1

DECISIONS UNDER RISK:

PROBABILITY

指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師報告者 : 曾阿玉日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

Page 2: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

2

OUTLINES3-1. Maximizing Expected Values3-2. Probability Theory

a. Bayes’s Theorem without Priors b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional

Information c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under

Ignorance

3-3. Interpretations of Probability a. The Classical View b. The Relative Frequency View c. Subjective Views d. Coherence and Conditionalization

3-4. References

Page 3: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

3

3-1. Maximizing Expected 3-1. Maximizing Expected ValuesValues

Page 4: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

4

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (1/7)

Case 1Case 1: Michael Smith applied to Peoples Insurance Company(PIC) for a life insurance policy in the amount of $25,000 at a premium of $100 for one year.

The decision whether or not to insure him became one under riskunder risk.

Smith Dies Smith Lives

Insure Smith -$25,000

.05 $100

.95

Do Not $0

.05 $0

.95

Page 5: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

5

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (2/7)

Case 2Case 2: Sally Harding needs a car for this year. She has a choice of buying an old heap for $400 and junk it at the end of the year, or a four-year-old car for $3,000 and sell it (net cost of the year comes to $500). If either breaks down, it costs about $200 to rent one.

Harding’s decision is again one under riskunder risk.

No Need to Rent Must Rent

Buy New -$500

.90 -$700

.10

Buy Old -$400

.50 -$600

.50

Page 6: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

6

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (3/7)

In Harding’s decision problem:

The probabilities of the states vary with the acts: (conditional on the acts)

The chances of Harding having to rent a car are a function of which car she buys.

The dominance principle should not be applied to this sort of case.

No Need to Rent Must Rent

Buy New -$500

.90 -$700

.10

Buy Old -$400

.50 -$600

.50

Page 7: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

7

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (4/7)

PIC’s case of Michael Smith:

PIC decided that they could not afford to insure Smith at a $100 premium. To insure a hundred people like Smith would - - cost the company $125,000 in death benefits - be counterbalanced by $10,000 net loss: $115,000

Their losses average close to $1,150 per person

Smith Dies Smith Lives

Insure Smith -$25,000

.05 $100

.95

Do Not $0

.05 $0

.95

Page 8: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

8

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (5/7)

PIC calculated the EMV for each act and chose the one with the highest EMVthe highest EMV.

Expected Monetary Value(EMV)Expected Monetary Value(EMV): From a decision table, multiply the monetary value in

each square by the probability number in that square and sum across the row.

- the EMV of insuring Smith is -$1,150 - the EMV of not insuring Smith is $0

Smith Dies Smith Lives

Insure Smith -$24,900-$24,900.05

$100 .95

Do Not $0

.05 $0

.95

Page 9: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

9

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (6/7)

For Sally Harding’s decision:

- the EMV of buying the newer car is -$520-$520 (-500)*0.9+(-700)*0.1=(-450)+(-70)= -520

- the EMV of buying the older one is -$500-$500 (-400)*0.5+(-600)*0.5=(-200)+(-300)= -500

Should Sally Harding buy the older car?Should Sally Harding buy the older car?

No Need to Rent Must Rent

Buy New -$500

.90 -$700

.10

Buy Old -$400

.50 -$600

.50

Page 10: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

10

3-1. Maximizing Expected Values (7/7)

Should Sally Harding buy the older car?Should Sally Harding buy the older car? On the averageOn the average, that would save her the most

money. ButBut,

what about the pleasures of riding in a newer car?what of the worry that the older one will break down?

PerhapsPerhaps, a revised set of EMVs will help. Sally Harding should be concerned with what happens to her, not to the average person like her.

Replacing monetary values with utility valuesutility values (maximizing EUVs)(maximizing EUVs)

Page 11: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

11

3-2. Probability Theory3-2. Probability Theory

Page 12: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

12

3-2. Probability Theory (1/23)

Probability judgments are now a commonplace of our daily life.

Probability is also essential to theoretical science. (It is the backbone of certain areas of physics, genetics, and the social sciences.)

Still much debate among philosophers, statisticians, and scientists concerning what prob. statements mean and how they may be justified or applied.

- Some believe that it is not proper to assign probabilities to single events, and hence that probability judgments inform us only of proportions; others believe that single events or statements can be assigned probabilities by simply refining our best hunches.

- Some believe that probability is a measure of the strength of beliefs or lack thereof; others think it is a property of reality.

Page 13: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

13

3-2. Probability Theory (2/23)

Probability calculusProbability calculus - A mathematical theory that enables us to calculate

additional probabilities from those we already know. For instance, if we know that the prob. that it will rain tomorrow is 50%, the prob. that gold price will drop tomorrow is 10%, then the calculus allows us to conclude that the prob.

that both will occur tomorrow is 5%. Probability calculus can be used with almost all the

interpretations of probability that have been proposed. Much of the superstructure of the theory of

decision under risk depends on the probability calculus.

Page 14: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

14

3-2. Probability Theory (3/23)

Absolute probability statementAbsolute probability statement

P(S)=aP(S)=a S: a statement form, such as "p or q", " p&q", or "p&(q or r)" a: a numeral.

Read as: "the probability of S is a.the probability of S is a."

Examples: P(p)=1/2, P(p or q)=2/3, P(not q or r)=0.9 In applications: P(the coin comes up heads)=1/2

P(heart or diamond)=1/2 P(ace and spade)=1/52

Page 15: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

15

3-2. Probability Theory (4/23)

Conditional probability statementConditional probability statement

P(S|W)=aP(S|W)=a Read as: "the probability of S given W=a.the probability of S given W=a."

Examples: The probability of drawing a heart at random from a

fair deck: P(heart)=1/4P(heart)=1/4 The probability of drawing a heart given that the card

to be drawn is red: P(heart|red)=1/2P(heart|red)=1/2 ≠≠ P(If the card is red, then it is a heart.)

= P(either the card is not red or it is a heart)=3/4 (Since, p→q ≡ p q)∼ ∨

Page 16: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

16

3-2. Probability Theory (5/23)

Important pointsImportant points: P(S|W) and P(W|S) are generally distinct. Ex: P(heart|red)=1/2, but P(red|heart)=1 Conditional and absolute probability are related,

however, through a number of laws of probability.

Ex: P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q|p) - The prob. of a conjunction is the prob. of the first

component times the prob. of the second given the first.

- It is less probable that two things will be true together than that either one will be true separately. (Since, prob.≤1)

Page 17: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

17

3-2. Probability Theory (6/23)

Important pointsImportant points: In general, we cannot simply multiply the prob. of 2

conjuncts, since their truth and falsity might be linked. Ex: P[heads and tails(on the same toss)]=0

= P(heads)xP(tails|heads)=1/2x0 ≠≠ P(heads)xP(tails)=1/2x1/2 =1/4

Example:Example: What is the prob. of drawing 2 aces in a row from an ordinary deck of 52 cards when the first card is not put back into the deck?

P(ace on draw1 and ace on draw2) = P(ace on draw1)xP(ace on draw2|ace on draw1) = 4/52x3/51=3/663.

Page 18: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

18

3-2. Probability Theory (7/23)

Last example illustrates: the outcome of the first draw(not replacednot replaced) affects the outcome of the second draw.

On the other hand, if the first card drawn is replacedreplaced and the deck reshuffled, the outcome of the first draw has no effect on the outcome of the second draw. (we say that the outcomes are independentindependent)

P(ace on draw2)=P(ace on draw2|ace on draw1)P(ace on draw2)=P(ace on draw2|ace on draw1)

Definition 1Definition 1: p is independentindependent of q if and only if P(p)=P(plq)P(p)=P(plq).

Page 19: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

19

3-2. Probability Theory (8/23)

Definition 2Definition 2:p and q are mutually exclusive mutually exclusive if and only if it is impossible for both to be trueimpossible for both to be true.

Ex: If a single card is drawn, then - drawing an ace and simultaneously drawing a king are mutually exclusive - drawing an ace and drawing a spade are not (one can draw the ace of spades) If p and q are mutually exclusive, if one is true the

other must be false. P(plq) and P(qlp) are 0. If p and q are mutually exclusive, p and q will not

be independent of each other- unless each already has a probability of 0.

Page 20: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

20

3-2. Probability Theory (9/23)

Axioms of the probability calculusAxioms of the probability calculus Axiom 1Axiom 1: a. 0≤P(p)≤1

b. 0≤P(p|q)≤1 Axiom 2Axiom 2: If p is certain, then P(p)=1. Axiom 3Axiom 3: If p and q are mutually exclusive, then

P(p or q)=P(p)+P(q). Ex: P(drawing an ace or a face card)

= 4/52+12/52 =16/52 =4/13 Theorem 1Theorem 1: P(p)+P(not p)=1. Pf: “p” and “not p” are mutually exclusive, (Axiom 3)

and their disjunction is certain. (Axiom 2) Thus we have: 1=P(p or not p)=P(p)+P(not p)

Page 21: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

21

3-2. Probability Theory (10/23)

Theorem 1 P(not p)=1- P(p)Ex: What is the probability of taking more than one

roll of a fair die to get a 6? The same as: not getting a 6 on the first roll,

P(not 6)=1-P(6)=1-1/6=5/6 Generalization Generalization of Theorem 1: The probabilities of any set of mutually exclusive and The probabilities of any set of mutually exclusive and

exhaustive alternatives sum to 1exhaustive alternatives sum to 1. (Alternatives are exhaustive if and only if it is certain

that at least one of them is true.) ※The probabilities in each row of a properly specified

decision table must total 1.

Page 22: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

22

3-2. Probability Theory (11/23)

Theorem 2Theorem 2: If p and q are equivalent, then P(p)=P(q).

Pf: Suppose that p and q are equivalent, then one is true just in case the other is.

1=P(not p or p) 1=P(not p or q) (Axiom 2) =P(not p)+P(q) (Axiom 3: mutually exclusive) =1-P(p)+P(q) (Theorem 1)

∴ P(p)=P(q)

Page 23: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

23

3-2. Probability Theory (12/23)

Theorem 3Theorem 3: P(p or q)=P(p)+P(q)-P(p&q).

Pf: "p or q" is logically equivalent to "either p&q or p& (not q) or else (not p)&q"

P(p or q) =P(either p&q or p& not q or else not p &q)

=P(either p&q or p& not q)+P(not p &q) =P(p)+P(not p &q)

Adding P(p&q) to both sides: P(p or q)+P(p&q)=P(p)+P(not p &q)+P(p&q)

=P(p)+P(q) ∴ P(p or q) =P(p)+P(q)-P(p&q)

Page 24: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

24

3-2. Probability Theory (13/23)

NoteNote: theorem 3 has axiom 3 as a special case; for when p and q are mutually exclusive P(p&q)=0.

Ex: P(a heart or a king)≠1/4 + 1/13 P(a heart or a king) = 1/4 + 1/13 – 1/52 - prevent double counting - prevent double counting when calculating prob. of

disjunctions whose components do not exclude each other.

Ex: What is the probability of getting exactly two heads on three tosses of a fair coin?

The 2 heads might occur in any one of 3 mutually exclusive ways: HHT, HTH, and THH.

∴ P(HHT)+P(HTH)+P(THH)=3/8

Page 25: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

25

3-2. Probability Theory (14/23)

Ex: What is the prob. of getting a heart or an ace on at least one of 2 draws from a deck of cards, where the card drawn is replaced and the deck reshuffled after the first draw?

P(getting a heart or an ace on the first draw)= 13/52+4/52-1/52 =16/52 =4/13.

But the prob. are the same for the second draw.

And the question allows for the possibility that a heart or an ace is drawn both times.

∴ The probability in question is 8/13

Page 26: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

26

3-2. Probability Theory (15/23)

Axiom 4Axiom 4: P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q|p). Theorem 4Theorem 4: If P(p)≠0, then P(q|p)= (conditional probabilityconditional probability)

Theorem 5Theorem 5: If q is independent of p, then P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q).

(By definition 1, if q is independent of p, P(q)=P(qlp))

Ex: What is the probability of getting twenty heads on twenty tosses of a fair coin ?

Each toss is independent of the othersEach toss is independent of the others, so the probability of getting 20 heads is (1/2)20

P(p)

q)&P(p

Page 27: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

27

3-2. Probability Theory (16/23)

Theorem 6Theorem 6: If p is independent of q if and only if q is independent of p, provided that P(p) and P(q) are both nonzero.

Pf: Suppose that both P(p) and P(q) are not zero. Suppose that p is independent of q. Then P(p) = P(plq). Then, by theorem 4, P(q|p)=P(p&q)/P(p) P(q|p)=[P(q)xP(p|q)]/P(p) =[P(q)xP(p)]/P(p)=P(q) ∴ q is independent of p By interchanging “q" and "p" in this proof, we can show that p is independent of q if q is independent of p.

Page 28: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

28

3-2. Probability Theory (17/23)

Theorem 7Theorem 7: If p and q are mutually exclusive and both P(p) and P(q) are nonzero, then p and q are not independent.

Pf: If p and q are mutually exclusive,then the negation of their conjunction is certain: P[not(p&q)]=1 and by theorem 1, then P(p&q)=0 If either p or q is independent of the other, then P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q)=0, which implies that P(p)=0 or P(q)=0. That would contradict the hypothesis of the theorem.

Page 29: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

29

3-2. Probability Theory (18/23)

NoteNote: The converse of theorem 7 does not hold: Independent statements need not be mutually exclusive

Ex: Getting heads on the second toss of a coin is independent of getting heads on the first toss, but they do not exclude each other.

Page 30: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

30

3-2. Probability Theory (19/23)

Theorem 8Theorem 8: (the Inverse Probability Lawthe Inverse Probability Law) If P(q)≠0, then P(p|q)=[P(p)xP(q|p)]/P(q).

Pf: Since "p&q" and “q&p" are equivalent, P(p&q)=P(q&p) (Theorem 2)

P(p)xP(q|p)=P(q)xP(p|q) (Axiom 4) By dividing by P(q), we have P(p|q)=[P(p)xP(q|p)]/P(q) #

.

Page 31: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

31

3-2. Probability Theory (20/23)

Theorem 9Theorem 9: (Bayes’s TheoremBayes’s Theorem)

If P(q)≠0, then P(p|q)=

Pf: By theorem 8 we have: P(p|q)=[P(p)xP(q|p)]/P(q).

But "q" is equivalent to "either p&q or not p &q."

By theorem 2, P(q)=P[(p&q) or (not p &q)]

= P(p&q)+P(not p &q) (Axiom 3: mutually exclusive)

= P(p)xP(q|p)+P(not p)xP(q|not p) (Axiom 4) ∴ P(p|q)=

p)]not |p)xP(q[P(not p)]|[P(p)xP(q

p)|P(p)xP(q

p)]not |p)xP(q[P(not p)]|[P(p)xP(q

p)|P(p)xP(q

Page 32: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

32

3-2. Probability Theory (21/23)

ExampleExample: A physician has just observed a spot on an X ray of some patient's lung.

Letting "S" stand for "the patient has a lung spot" "TB" stand for "the patient has tuberculosis"

Assume that P(S),P(TB),P(S|TB) are known by him. By applying the inverse probability law the physician can calculate the probability that the patient has TB given that he has a lung spot.

P(TB|S)=

P(TB): prior probability of TB (probability assigned before the spot was observed)

P(TB|S): posterior probability of TB

P(S)

TB)|P(TB)xP(S

Page 33: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

33

3-2. Probability Theory (22/23)

Cont.Cont.: It is likely that a physician can easily find out the prob. of observing lung spots given that a patient has TB, and the prob.of a patient's having TB.(since there are much medical data)

But it is less likely that a physician will have access to data concerning the prob. of observing lung spots per se.

Then the inverse probability law will not apply, but Bayes's theorem might.

For suppose the physician knows that the patient has TB or lung cancer(LC) but not both.

P(TB|S)=

LC)|P(LC)P(STB)|P(TB)xP(S

TB)|P(TB)xP(S

Page 34: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

34

3-2. Probability Theory (23/23)

ExampleExample: Suppose P(Rain)=0.25, P(Clouds)=0.4, P(Clouds|Rain)=1,You observe a cloudy sky. Now what are the chances of rain?

Using the inverse probability law:

P(Rain|Clouds)=

= =

P(Clouds)

Rain)|CloudsP(Rain)xP(

0.4

0.25x1

8

5

Page 35: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

35

3-2. Problems (1/4)Problems (1/4)

1. Assume a card is drawn at random from an ordinary fifty-two card deck. a. What is the probability of drawing an ace? b. The ace of hearts? c. The ace of hearts or the king of hearts? d. An ace or a heart?

2. A card is drawn and not replaced, then another card is drawn. a. What is the probability of the ace of hearts on the first draw and the king of hearts on the second? b. What is the probability of two aces? c. What is the probability of no ace on either draw? d. What is the probability of at least one ace and at least one heart for the two draws?

Page 36: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

36

3-2. Problems (2/4)Problems (2/4)

3. P(p)=1/2, P(q)=1/2, P(p&q)=1/4. Are p and q mutually exclusive? What is P(p or q)?

4. A die is loaded so that the probability of rolling a 2 is twice that of a 1, that of a 3 three times that of a 1, that of a 4 four times that of a 1, etc. What is the probability of rolling an odd number?

5. Prove that if "p" implies "q" and P(p)≠0, then P(q/p)=1. (Hint:"p" implies "q" just in case "p" is equivalent to "p&q")

6. Prove that P(p&q)≤P(p).

7. Suppose that P(p)=1/4, P(qlp)=1, P(q|not p)=1/5. Find P(p|q).

Page 37: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

37

3-2. Problems (3/4)Problems (3/4)

8. There is a room filled with urns of two types. Type I urns contain six blue balls and four red balls; urns of type II contain nine red balls and one blue ball. There are 800 type I urns and 200 type II urns in the room. They are distributed randomly and look alike. An urn is selected from the room and a ball drawn from it.

a. What is the (prior) probability of the urn's being type I? b. What is the probability that the ball drawn is red? c. What is the probability that the ball drawn is blue? d. If a blue ball is drawn, what is the (posterior) probability that the urn is of type I? e. What is it if a red ball is drawn?

Page 38: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

38

3-2. Problems (4/4)Problems (4/4)

9. Suppose you could be certain that the urn in the last example is of type II. Explain why seeing a blue ball drawn from the urn would not produce a lower posterior probability for the urn being of type II.

Page 39: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

39

3-2a. 3-2a. Bayes’s Theorem without Bayes’s Theorem without PriorsPriors

Page 40: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

40

3-2a. Bayes’s Theorem without Priors (1/5)

ExampleExample: Suppose you are traveling in a somewhat magical land where some of the coins are biased to land tails 75% of the time.

- You find a coin and you and a friend try to determine whether the coin is biased.

- You do not have any magnets to test the coin. - So you flip the coin ten times. Each time the coin lands

tails up.

Can you conclude that the coin is more likely to be Can you conclude that the coin is more likely to be biased than not?biased than not?

It would seem natural to try to apply Bayes's theorem (or the inverse probability law) here. But what is the what is the prior probabilityprior probability that the coin is biasedthat the coin is biased?

Page 41: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

41

3-2a. Bayes’s Theorem without Priors (2/5)

Some statisticians and decision theorists claim:In a situation such as this you should take your best hunch as the prior probability and use it to apply Bayes's theorem. (Bayesians)(Bayesians)

BayesiansBayesians::

- Desire to use Bayes's theorem (when other statisticians believe it should not be applied).

- Constructed an argument in support of their position that is itself based on Bayes's theorem.

Page 42: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

42

3-2a. Bayes’s Theorem without Priors (3/5)

Bayesian’s argument: Suppose you come to a situation in which you use your best

hunch (or hunches) to estimate the prior probability that some statement p is true.

Next suppose you are exposed to a large amount of data bearing on the truth of p and you use Bayes's theorem or the inverse probability law to generate posterior probabilities for the truth of p, taking the posterior probabilities so yielded as their new priors, and repeat this process each time you receive new data.

Then as you are exposed to more and more data your probability estimates will come closer and closer to the "objective" or statistically based probability—if there is one.

Furthermore, if several individuals are involved, their several (and possibly quite different) personal probability estimates will converge to each other.

The claim is that, in effect, large amounts of data bearing on the truth of p can "wash out" poor initial probability

estimates.

Page 43: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

43

3-2a. Bayes’s Theorem without Priors (4/5)

Return to the last example: Suppose that before you decided to toss the coin you

assigned a probability of .01 to its being biased (B) and a probability of .99 to its being not biased (not B).

Each toss of the coin is independent of the others, so the probabilities of ten tails in a row conditional on either coin are: P(10 tails|B)=(3/4)10

P(10 tails|not B)=(1/2)10

Calculate the ratio :

= =

= (.01x(3/4)10)/(.99x(1/2)10) =(1/99)(3/2)10 ≈ 57.7

tails) B)]/P(10 not|tails B)xP(10 [P(not

tails) B)]/P(10|tails [P(B)xP(10tails) 10|BP(not

tails) 10|P(B

B)] not|tails B)xP(10 [P(not

B)]|tails [P(B)xP(10

Page 44: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

44

3-2a. Bayes’s Theorem without Priors (5/5)

If you had flipped it a hundred times and had gotten a hundred tails, the probability of its being biased would be over 3,000 times larger than its being not biased.

More complicated mathematics is required to analyze the cases in which some proportion of the tosses are heads while the balance are tails. It is not hard to show, for example, that if 1/4 of the tosses turned out to be heads, that you would assign a higher probability to the coin's being biased, and that the probability would increase as the number of tosses did.

Page 45: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

45

3-2a. ProblemsProblems

1. Calculate the posterior probability that the coin is biased given that you flip the coin ten times and observe eight tails followed by two heads. [P(B)=0.01]2. Calculate the posterior probability that the coin is biased given that you flip it ten times and observe any combination of eight tails and two heads. [P(B)=0.01] 3. Suppose you assigned a probability of 0 to the coin's being biased. Show that, no matter how many tails in a row you observed, neither Bayes's theorem nor the inverse probability law would lead to a nonzero posterior probability for the coin's being biased.

Page 46: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

46

3-2b. 3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem Bayes’s Theorem andand

the Value of Additional the Value of Additional InformationInformation

Page 47: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

47

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (1/9)

Another important application application of Bayes's theorem and the inverse probability law in decision theory is their use to determine the value of additional to determine the value of additional informationinformation.

- having more facts on which to base a decision can make a radical difference to our choices.But how can we determine how much those facts are worth?

In decisions under risk the choices the choices we make are a a function offunction of the values we assign to outcomesvalues we assign to outcomes and the probabilities we assign to statesprobabilities we assign to states.

Page 48: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

48

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (2/9)

As we obtain more information we often revise our probability assignments.

- Often, by using Bayes's theorem or the inverse probability law, we can calculate:how our probabilities and decisions probabilities and decisions would change and how much our expectations expectations would be raised.The latter may be used to determine upper bounds upper bounds on the value of that informationon the value of that information.

There are many applications of this technique ranging from evaluating diagnostic tests in medicine to designing surveys for business and politics to the evaluation of scientific research programs.

Page 49: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

49

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (3/9)

ExampleExample: Clark is deciding whether to invest $50,000 in the Daltex Oil Company.

- He has heard a rumor that Daltex will sell shares of stock publicly within the year. If that happens he will double his money; otherwise he will earn only the unattractive return of 5 % for the year and would be better off taking his other choice — buying a 10% savings certificate.

- He believes there is about an even chance about an even chance that Daltex will go public.

Page 50: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

50

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (4/9)

Decision table 3-3

Clark makes his decisions on the basis of expected expected monetary valuesmonetary values; so he has tentatively decided to invest in Daltex since that has an EMV of $76,250.

EMV1=100,000x0.5+52,500 x0.5=76,250 EMV2=55,000x0.5+55,000 x0.5=55,000

Table 3-3Daltex Goes

PublicDoes Not

Invest in Daltex $100,000

.5 $52,500

.5

Buy a Savings Certificate

$55,000 .5

$55,000 .5

Page 51: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

51

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (5/9)

SupposeSuppose he could pay some completely reliable person to tell him now whether Daltex will go public.

- If he learned that Daltex was certain to go public, his EMV would increase to $100,000, whereasif he learned that it was certain not to go public, he would buy the savings certificate and decrease his EMV to $55,000.

- He believes that he has an even chance even chance of learning either piece of information.

ThusThus his expectations prior to prior to paying the completely reliable person for the truth about Daltex are $100,000x(.5)+$55,000x(.5)=$77,500. $77,500-$76,250=$1,250$77,500-$76,250=$1,250

Page 52: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

52

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (6/9)

SupposeSuppose that Clark knows Daltex is preparing a confidential annual report and he also knows that:

- If they are going public there is a chance of 0.9 that they will say so in the report and only a 0.1 chance that they will deny it.

- If they are not going public there is a chance of 0.5 that they will say that they are not and 0.5 chance that they will lie and say they are.

- Clark knows someone in Daltex who will show him a copy of the report—for a price.

Page 53: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

53

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (7/9)

SoSo he decides to use Bayes's theoremBayes's theorem to calculate the probabilities that Daltex will (will not) go public given that they say (deny) that they will in the report.

P(P|Y)=

= = 0.64+

Similarly, P(not PIY)=0.35+; P(P|N)=0.16+; P(not PIN)=0.83+

Clark then considers twotwo revised decision tables—one based on the probabilities he would use after reading an affirmationaffirmation of going public, the other based on those he would use after reading a denialdenial.

P) not|P)xP(Y P(notP)|P(P)xP(Y

P)|P(P)xP(Y

0.5x0.50.5x0.9

0.5x0.9

Page 54: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

54

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (8/9)

- Reading an affirmationaffirmation

EMV1=100,000x0.643+52,500 x0.357=83042.5 EMV2=55,000

- Reading a denialdenial

EMV1=100,000x0.167+52,500 x0.833=60432.5 EMV2=55,000

On either version, the EMV of investing in Daltex would still be higher than that of buying the savings certificate.

So he decides not to not to offer the bribe.

Page 55: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

55

3-2b. Bayes’s Theorem and the Value of Additional Information (9/9)

By changing the example appropriately we can arrange for Clark to discover that reading a denial in the report would change his original decisionchange his original decision.He would then proceed to calculate the gains calculate the gains he can expect under the two scenarios and average these average these to find the maximum price he should pay to see the report.

When nonmonetarynonmonetary values are involved, as happens in medicine or science, it may also be necessary to enlist some advanced ideas in utility theoryutility theory.

Page 56: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

56

3-2b. Problems (1/2)Problems (1/2) 1. Suppose P(Y|P)=0.0l, P(N|P)=0.99, P(YInot P)=0.5, and P(NInot P)=0.5. How much should Clark be willing to pay to see the report?

2. A closet contains 800 type I urns and 200 type two urns. Urns of both types appear identical but type I urns contain six blue balls and four red ones; type II urns contain one blue ball and nine red ones. An urn is drawn at random from the closet and you must bet on the type of the urn. If you bet on type I and it is one, you win $20, otherwise you lose $10. If you bet on type II and it is one, you win $80, otherwise you lose $10. Assume that you maximize expected monetary values. (to be continued… )

Page 57: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

57

3-2b. Problems (2/2)Problems (2/2)

a. Set up a decision table for the choice between the two bets and calculate the EMVs of the two bets. Which one would you choose? b. Prior to making your choice, what is the maximum amount you should pay to learn the type of the urn? c. Assume that a blue ball has been drawn from the urn. Appropriately revise your table and calculate the new EMVs. Which bet would you choose now? d. Assume that the ball drawn is red and then follow the rest of the instructions for c. e. Prior to seeing the ball and making your choice, what is the maximum amount that you should pay to see it?

Page 58: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

58

3-2c. 3-2c. Statistical Decision TheoryStatistical Decision Theory and and

Decisions under IgnoranceDecisions under Ignorance

Page 59: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

59

3-2c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under Ignorance (1/6)

Several of the rules for making decisions under ignorance were originally developed by statisticiansby statisticians for handling statistical problems for handling statistical problems in which some of the datadata necessary for applying Bayes's theorem are unavailableunavailable.

A typical problem in applied statisticsA typical problem in applied statistics—the predicament faced by a drug company that needs to test a new batch of pills prior to marketing them.

- Their usual practice usual practice is to test new lots by feeding some of the pills to a hundred rats and observing how many die.

- From their previous experience previous experience with this and similar drugs, they have developed good estimates good estimates of the percentage of rats that will die if the batch is defective.

Page 60: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

60

3-2c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under Ignorance (2/6)

- UnfortunatelyUnfortunately, due to an irregularityirregularity in making this particular batch, the staff has no idea of the prob. of its being defective.

Suppose the test is run and five rats die.Suppose the test is run and five rats die.Since the rats in our laboratory die from time to time from various other causes, the staff cannot be certain that the pills are defective.

Can theyCan they use the test results to calculate the prob. of use the test results to calculate the prob. of the batch's being defective?the batch's being defective?They could use Bayes's theorem if they could assign a prob. to the batch's being defective prior to prior to running the test. But But that is exactly the probability they cannot assign.

Page 61: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

61

3-2c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under Ignorance (3/6)

Bayesian statisticians Bayesian statisticians would urge the staff to try to use their best hunches best hunches as the prior probability that the batch is defective.And offer some methods for refining and checking these hunches.

Many statisticians dissent from this and urge that the problem be treated as one under ignoranceunder ignorance.

- But it is not as simple as a two-act/two-state choice: marketing or not marketing against possibilities of the batch's being fine or being defective

for that would not respond to the test resultsthat would not respond to the test results.

Page 62: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

62

3-2c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under Ignorance (4/6)

They have proposed thatprior prior to running the test we should choose between various strategies various strategies for responding to the test resultstest results.

For instance, we might adopt the strategy of marketing the pills no matter how many rats die or marketing them if no more than two die or not marketing them at all.

ThenThen after the test is run we market or withhold the pills according to the prescriptions of the strategyaccording to the prescriptions of the strategy we have selected.This allows the test results to influence our actions without depending on guesses as to the prior probability that the batch is defective.

Page 63: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

63

3-2c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under Ignorance (5/6)

How do we choose a strategy? How do we choose a strategy? - We presumably know the valuevalue of marketing of marketing defective

(or good) pills and the value of withholding value of withholding them. - Use the probabilities that various percentages of the

rats die given that the batch is defective (or fine) to calculate the various expected values of our strategiescalculate the various expected values of our strategies under the assumption that the batch is defectivedefective,and we can make similar calculations under the assumption that it is finefine.(Using this we can form decision table 3-4)

- FinallyFinally, we can apply one of the rules for making apply one of the rules for making decisions under ignorance decisions under ignorance to table 3-4.

Page 64: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

64

3-2c. Statistical Decision Theory and Decisions under Ignorance (6/6)

This certainly does not settle the philosophical and methodological issues raised by the absence of prior probabilities.

We must once again face the question of the proper proper rule to userule to use for making our decision under ignorance.

Table 3-4 Batch Defective Batch fine

Strategy 1 x y

Strategy 2 z w

::

::

::

Strategy n u v

Page 65: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

65

3-2c. Problems (1/4)Problems (1/4)

1. Suppose you formulate strategies as depending on whether fewer than ten rats die or whether ten or more die. This yields four strategies.

Two are:

(1) market if fewer than ten die; market if ten or more die; (2) market if fewer than ten die; withhold if ten or more die.

List the remaining two.

Page 66: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

66

3-2c. Problems (2/4)Problems (2/4)

2. Suppose that the probability that ten or more rats die given that the batch is defective is 0.5 and that it is 0.01 given that the batch is fine. Construct two tables—one assuming that the batch is defective, the other that it is fine—that will tabulate your probabilities of marketing and withholding the pills under each strategy. (For example, in the row for strategy 2 of the first table there is a probability of 0.5 that you will market and one of 0.5 that you will withhold.) These tables give your action probabilities.

Page 67: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

67

3-2c. Problems (3/4)Problems (3/4)

3. Now assume that your value for marketing a defective batch is -1,000, for marketing a fine one is 100, for withholding a defective one is 0, and for withholding a fine one is -100. Use these values and your action probabilities to calculate the expected values for each strategy under the assumption that the batch is defective. Do the same under the assumption that it is fine. (For example, the first value for the second strategy is -500 or [.5][-1000] + [.5][0].) This should enable you to complete table 3-5.

(to be continued… )

Page 68: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

68

3-2c. Problems (4/4)Problems (4/4)

If you use the maximin rule, which strategy do you choose? Do you think this is the only reasonable choice to make in this situation?

Table 3-5 Batch Defective Batch fine

Strategy 1

Strategy 2 -500

Strategy 3

Strategy 4

Page 69: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

69

3-3. Interpretations of 3-3. Interpretations of ProbabilityProbability

Page 70: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

70

3-3. Interpretations of Probability (1/3)

There are many contending views concerning— - what probability statements mean - when and how they may be applied - how their truth may be ascertained

Classification of the interpretations of probability

- Objective views Logical

Empirical

- Subjective views A satisfactory interpretation of probability must

satisfy the probability calculus.

Page 71: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

71

3-3. Interpretations of Probability (2/3)

Objective viewsObjective views: see probability as measuring something independent of human judgmentsindependent of human judgments, and constant from person to person.

LogicalLogical: count probability as a property defined in terms of logical or mathematical structures

EmpiricalEmpirical: as an empirically defined property

Subjective viewsSubjective views: regard probability as the measure of an individual's belief or confidencean individual's belief or confidence in a statement and permit it to vary from person to person.

Page 72: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

72

3-3. Interpretations of Probability (3/3)

ExamplesExamples: an asserted statement:

The probability that 2/3 of the next 100 tosses of this The probability that 2/3 of the next 100 tosses of this coin will land head up is .75coin will land head up is .75

- - Subjective views: meaning that I am reasonably confident that 2/3 of the tosses will result in heads.

- Logical views: reflecting a logical or mathematical analysis of the various possible tosses and (perhaps) my evidence concerning them.

- Empirical views: see it as about the behavior of the coin and as testable in terms of it.

Page 73: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

73

3-3a. 3-3a. The Classical ViewThe Classical View

Page 74: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

74

3-3a. The Classical View (1/8)

The Classical ViewThe Classical View also known as the the Laplacean viewLaplacean view.

(named after one of its founders)

the oldest and simplest view of probability.

an objective and logical view

best applied to games of chance and other clearly specified situations that can be divided into a number of equally likely cases.

Ex: random card drawings, tosses of fair coins, and rolls of unloaded dice

Page 75: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

75

3-3a. The Classical View (2/8)

The Classical ViewThe Classical ViewLet us think of each statement p as having a finite a finite set of possibilitiesset of possibilities associated with it.p-cases: the possibilities that verify the statement

Ex: statement: "The coin will land heads in at least one of the next two tosses" is associated with the four possible outcomes of tossing the coin twice (HH, HT, TH, TT).

General formGeneral form: the probability of p is the ratio of the number of p-cases to the total number of cases or possibilities

P(p) = #(p-cases)/#(total possibilities) P(p) = #(p-cases)/#(total possibilities)

Page 76: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

76

3-3a. The Classical View (3/8)

Conditional probabilityConditional probability

P(q|p) is the number of p-cases that are also q-cases. When there are no p-cases, it is zero.

P(qlp)= #(p&q-cases)/#(p-cases)P(qlp)= #(p&q-cases)/#(p-cases) if #(p-cases)>0 = 0= 0 if #(p-cases)=0

Ex: Consider the probability that the card you have drawn is an ace given that it is a heart.

P(ace|heart)= #(aces)/ #(hearts) = 1/13.

Page 77: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

77

3-3a. The Classical View (4/8)

ProbabilityProbability calculuscalculus

Axiom 1Axiom 1: a. 0≤P(p)≤1 b. 0≤P(p|q)≤1

For: The number of possibilities associated with a statement is never negative, and

The number of p-cases (p & q-cases) never exceeds the total number of cases (the number of p-cases).

Thus: P(p) [P(q|p)] must be a number between 0 and 1 inclusively.

Page 78: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

78

3-3a. The Classical View (5/8)

Probability calculusProbability calculus Axiom 2Axiom 2: If p is certain, then P(p)=1.

For: A certainty is true no matter what;

Thus: The cases in which it is true must be identical with all the cases associated with it and the ratio of the number of the one to that of the other must be 1.

Page 79: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

79

3-3a. The Classical View (6/8)

Probability calculusProbability calculus

Axiom 3Axiom 3: If p and q are mutually exclusive, then P(p or q)=P(p)+P(q).

For: "p or q" is construed as meaning that either p is true, q is true, or both p and q are true. If p and q are mutually exclusive, the (p or q)- cases are simply the cases in which either p or q (but not the other) is true.

P(p or q)= #[(p or q)-cases]/#(total cases)= #p-cases/#(total cases)+#q-cases/#(total cases)= P(p)+P(q)

Page 80: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

80

3-3a. The Classical View (7/8)

Probability calculusProbability calculus

Axiom 4Axiom 4: P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q|p).

Let’s distinguish two cases:- those p for which there are nono p-cases.- those for which there are somesome.

In the first case:Both P(p) and P(qlp) are 0.Since every p&q-case is a p-case, P(p&q) is 0.

Thus, P(p&q)=0=P(p)xP(qlp)

Page 81: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

81

3-3a. The Classical View (8/8)

Probability calculusProbability calculus In the second case:

P(q|p)= #(p&q-cases)/#(p-cases) But we have,

P(p&q)= #(p&q-cases)/#(total cases) P(p)= #(p-cases)/#(total cases)

Whence, P(p)xP(q|p)= [#(p-cases)/#(total cases)] x[#(p&q-cases)/#(p-cases)] = #(p&q-cases)/#(total cases) = P(p&q)

Axiom 4 holds for both of the distinguished cases.

Page 82: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

82

3-3a. ProblemsProblems

1. Use the technique of this section to show directly that theorem 1 holds under the classical interpretation.

2. Do the same for theorem 2.

Page 83: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

83

3-3a. The Classical View (1/10)

Objections to this approachObjections to this approach

Some can be overcome by enlisting the technical

machinery of modern logic and mathematics.

Others remain obstacles to the acceptance of even

up-dated versions of the classical view.

Page 84: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

84

3-3a. The Classical View (2/10)

Relatively technical problem:

The present version assumes that a definite finite set a definite finite set of possibilities is associated with each statementof possibilities is associated with each statement.

A simple matter when we are talking about— - tossing coins

- spinning roulette wheels - drawing cards

Page 85: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

85

3-3a. The Classical View (3/10)

What happens when talking about the prob. of—

- another world war- being successful in a career or marriage- a drought

What are the relevant possibilities here?How do we combine the possibilities needed for

compound statements?How do we relate the probability that you will have a good

career and the probability that you will have a happy marriage to the probability that you will have both?

The classical view has no ready answers to these The classical view has no ready answers to these questions.questions.

Page 86: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

86

3-3a. The Classical View (4/10)

The classical view even has problems with the simple questions which it was designed to handle.

Example: How do we compute the probability of getting two heads in two tosses of the same fair coin?

Compute #1: There are four cases: HH, HT, TH, TT; one is verifying, so the probability is 1/4.

Compute #2: There are three cases: HH, HT, TT; thus the probability is 1/3.

First computation is the right one.First computation is the right one. But the classical view does not tell us thatBut the classical view does not tell us that.

Page 87: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

87

3-3a. The Classical View (5/10)

Logicians have partially solved the problem of specifying sets of relevant possibilities.

- They have used precise, limited, and technical languages for formulating those statements to which probabilities are to be assigned and then have defined the associated sets of possibilities in terms of statements within such languages.

Page 88: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

88

3-3a. The Classical View (6/10)

Example: To describe the tosses of a coinTo describe the tosses of a coin

We can introduce a language with two individual constants, "a" and “b" —

a -designate the side that comes up on the first tossb -designate the one that comes up on the second toss

and one predicate "H" for heads. (Tails as "not H")

Then the relevant set of possibilities for two tosses of the coin can be specified as those statements of the language that affirm or deny that the coin comes up heads on either toss.

These yield the four possibilities:Ha, HbHa, Hb; ; Ha, not HbHa, not Hb; ; not Ha, Hbnot Ha, Hb; ; not Ha, not Hbnot Ha, not Hb.

Page 89: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

89

3-3a. The Classical View (7/10)

This method is limited by our ability to construct artificial languages and specify possibilities within them.

Acute limitation: when trying to use the classical approach to assign probabilities to statements involving an indefinite or infinite number of cases.

ex: Try to assign a probability to the statement that there will be an atomic holocaust sometime.

Technical developments in logic will solve such problems Technical developments in logic will solve such problems eventually. eventually.

Page 90: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

90

3-3a. The Classical View (8/10)

Another objection: The classical approach depend on the assumption

that each of the possibilities associated with a each of the possibilities associated with a statement is equally likelystatement is equally likely.

ex: In assigning a probability of 1/2 to getting heads on a toss of a fair coin. (Since the calculation assumes that we should give equal weight to getting heads and to getting tails.)

But how do we know that each case is equally likely? What does "equally likely" mean in this context?

Page 91: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

91

3-3a. The Classical View (9/10)

Two courses are open - Invoking some other conception of probability Invoking some other conception of probability to

explain and justify the assumption that each case is

equally likely. ex: : The claim The claim that getting heads is just as likely as

getting tails means that in a long series of tosses of the coin, the proportion of heads will bethe proportion of heads will be approximately the same as the proportion of tails approximately the same as the proportion of tails.

-> The classical view is an idealizationidealization of a more properly experimental approach to probability. The classical approach is to be used as a shortcut approximationapproximation.

Page 92: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

92

3-3a. The Classical View (10/10)

Two courses are open - The assignment of the same weight to each

possibility is simply an assumption that is so fundamental so fundamental that further attempts to justify it are fruitless.

Some even claim that this assumption—which they have dubbed the principle of insufficient reason—is, self-evidentself-evident.

Page 93: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

93

3-3b. 3-3b. The Relative Frequency The Relative Frequency ViewView

Page 94: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

94

The classical view is devoid of empirical content. Because its probabilities are ultimately ratios ultimately ratios involving

abstract possibilities,

a classically interpreted probability statement has no implications concerning actual events and can be neither confirmed nor refuted by them.

The relative frequency view is an objective and empirical view.

It defines probability in terms of actual events.

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (1/10)

Page 95: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

95

Presentation of the probability calculus - Assign probabilities to either classes, kinds, or

properties of events rather than to statements.

- View all probabilities as implicitly conditional.

P(S)=aP(S)=a and P(S|W)=bP(S|W)=b

PPRR(S)=a(S)=a and PPR R (S|W)=b(S|W)=b

Reading these as:

the probability that an R is an S an R is an S equals a the probability that an R is an S given that it is a Wan R is an S given that it is a W equals b

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (2/10)

Page 96: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

96

Probability statements no longer make assertions about statements but instead make assertions about classes, properties, or kinds of events.

ExampleExample: Instead of saying---

the probability assigned to the statement that this coin will land heads on the next toss is 1/2. The frequentist says--- the probability that a toss of this coin (an event) is a toss of this coin (an event) is one in which it lands heads (another event) one in which it lands heads (another event) is 1/2.

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (3/10)

Page 97: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

97

Relative frequentists hold that probabilities are proportions or relative frequencies of events of one kind to those of others.

- Interpretation of probability- Interpretation of probability PR(P)=a means the proportion of Rs that are Ps is a

i.e., #(P&Rs)/#(Rs)=a

- Interpretation of conditional probability- Interpretation of conditional probability PR(Q|P) = #(P&Q&Rs)/#(P&Rs).

= 0 if nothing is both a P and an R.

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (4/10)

Page 98: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

98

Example: 2 statements

1. The probability that an airplane flying from New York to London crashes is 1/1,000,000.

2. The probability that an airplane flying from New York to London crashes given that it has engine failure is 1/10.

-> If we were to inspect the record inspect the record of flights from New York to London we would find that only one in a million crashes.

-> If we were to keep a record keep a record of those flights from New York to London that also experienced engine failures, we would find that the crash rate increased to 1 in 10.

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (5/10)

Page 99: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

99

ProbabilityProbability calculuscalculus

Axiom 1Axiom 1: a. 0≤PR(P)≤1 b. 0≤PR (Q|P)≤1

For: The relative frequency interpretation of PR(P) is concerned with the proportion of events of kind P

among those of kind R. It is thus a ratio between 0 and 1 inclusively.

Since the same is easily shown for PR (Q|P) as well, the interpretation satisfies axiom 1.

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (6/10)

Page 100: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

100

ProbabilityProbability calculuscalculus

Axiom 2Axiom 2: If P is certain, then PR(P)=1.

For: If every R is certain to be a P,

then the ratio of Ps to Rs is 1 and PR(P) = 1.

PR(P)= #(P&Rs)/#(Rs)=1

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (7/10)

Page 101: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

101

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (8/10)

ProbabilityProbability calculuscalculus

Axiom 3Axiom 3: If P and Q are mutually exclusive, (no event can be both a P and a Q) then PR(P or Q)=PR(P)+PR(Q).

For: This just means showing that the proportion of Ps among the Rs plusplus the proportion of Qs among the Rs isis just the proportion of the (P or Q)s among the Rs.

And that must certainly be the case when no R can no R can be both P and Qbe both P and Q

Page 102: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

102

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (9/10)

Probability calculusProbability calculus

Axiom 4Axiom 4: PR(P&Q)=PR(P)xPR(Q|P).

Let’s distinguish two cases:- those P for which there are none among the Rnone among the Rs.- those for which there are somesome.

In the first case:Both PR(P) and PR(QlP) are 0.Since every P&Q must be a P, PR(P&Q) is 0.

Thus, PR(P&Q) =0=PR(P)xPR(Q|P)

Page 103: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

103

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (10/10)

Probability calculusProbability calculus

In the second case:PR(Q|P) = #(P&Q&Rs)/#(P&Rs)

But we have,PR(P&Q)= #(P&Q&Rs)/#(Rs) PR(P)= #(P&Rs)/#(Rs)

Whence,PR(P)xPR(Q|P)= [#(P&Rs)/#(Rs)] x[#(P&Q&Rs)/#(P&Rs)] = #(P&Q&Rs)/#(Rs) = PR(P&Q)

Axiom 4 holds for both of the distinguished cases.

Page 104: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

104

3-3b. ProblemsProblems

1. Verify axiom 4.

2. Do the same for theorem 2.

Page 105: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

105

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (1/9)

Given the way in which it has been specified, the relative frequency view have problems with---

indefinite and infinite indefinite and infinite totalities

determining the frequency of heads in the tosses of the dime

- For no one can currently specify its total number of tosses.

Page 106: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

106

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (2/9)

However, mathematical improvements mathematical improvements on the relative frequency view can handle cases like this one and give them empirical content.

Very roughly, we toss the coin again and again and after each toss note the proportion of heads note the proportion of heads among the tosses among the tosses to that point.

If these ratios appear to be tending to a limit pointtending to a limit point, then that limit is identified with the probabilityprobability of getting heads on a given toss of the coin.

We might call this "the long-run frequency" "the long-run frequency" approach to probabilityapproach to probability.

Page 107: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

107

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (3/9)

Either frequency approach has the obvious advantage over the classical view of not being circular.Nor does the frequency approach require dubious assumptions, such as the principle of insufficient reason, and it extends to the indefinite/infinite case with greater ease than does the classical approach.

The relative frequency approach has a less firm grip less firm grip on "true" probabilitieson "true" probabilities than the classical approach.

Page 108: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

108

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (4/9)

Consider the question again Consider the question again of the frequency of heads in tosses of the dime:

- A theorem of the probability calculus entails that if the probability of heads is 1/2, the frequencies of these tosses will converge to 1/2 in the long runconverge to 1/2 in the long run.

- Another theorem entails that ultimate convergence to 1/2 is compatible with any initial finite sequence of tosses consisting entirely of headsentirely of heads.

Now suppose the dime were tossed 10,000 times and it came up heads 90% of the time. Most Most relative frequentists would be willing to stop the tossing, proclaim that the coin is most probably biased and that the true probability of heads is close to 9/10. (to be continued…)

Page 109: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

109

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (5/9)

- But it could turn out that after the first 10,000 tosses heads start to appear so often that the long-run frequency is 1/2.

On the frequency view, 1/2 would be the true probability, although the initial observations belied it.

Putting the point more generally, there is simply no no guaranteeguarantee that the frequencies observed to date to date are even close to the long-run frequency.

The classical view does not face this problem because it cuts itself off from observation.

(But that does not seem to be much of an advantage either; for if it did turn up heads on every one of 10,000 tosses, even fans of the classical view would be hard pressed to justify taking 1/2 as the probability of getting heads.)

Page 110: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

110

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (6/9)

The frequency view cannot make sense of assigning probabilities to single events or statements. (for it specifies probabilities in terms of proportions)

Ex: if you ask a frequentist what is the probability that you will pass your final exam in English.

He can only speak to you of the percentage --- - of students in the course that will pass - of the percentage of those tests you take that you pass - of the percentage of those like you in certain relevant respects who will pass, and so on…But refusing to assign a probability to the single case of your passing.

Page 111: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

111

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (7/9)

Propensity interpretations of probability

- One version of this view construes probabilities as the frequencies predictedthe frequencies predicted by the relevant theoretical laws.

Since predicted frequencies may differ from those actually observed, this account is not thrown by my dime coming up heads on the first 10,000 tosses.

That happening with most dimes would strongly signal something wrong with any theory that predicts a frequency of 1/2, and we would take steps to revise it.

- The propensity view responds to observation without following it slavishly.

Page 112: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

112

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (8/9)

Single-case propensity Single-case propensity interpretation countenances assigning probabilities to single events.

ex: Consider the dime again: One should be able to design a device for tossing it that would favor neither heads nor tails. Such a device would have a propensity of 1/2 to yield heads on its tosses. More important, it would have a propensity of 1/2 to yield a head on any particular toss.

- By identifying probabilities with such single-case propensities we could make sense of assigning probabilities to single events.

Page 113: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

113

3-3b. The Relative Frequency View (9/9)

There are limits to the applicability of the propensity approach.

- Often we do not know enough to discern propensities.

ex: Physicians know that heart disease is much more frequent among heavy smokers, but currently they have no way of knowing whether any individual heavy smoker has a higher propensity

for developing heart disease than some other one does.

- It does not always make sense to speak of propensities where we can significantly speak of probabilities.

Page 114: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

114

3-3c. 3-3c. Subjective ViewsSubjective Views

Page 115: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

115

3-3c. Subjective Views (1/31)

The logical approach The logical approach to probability fails in situations where we lack the analytic resources it presupposes.

The frequency approach The frequency approach breaks down on single-case probabilities.

The propensity approach The propensity approach fails to cover cases where propensities are not known or do not make sense.

The subjective approach The subjective approach to probability is an attempt to develop a notion of probability that meets all these challenges.

Page 116: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

116

3-3c. Subjective Views (2/31)

Subjective probabilities are personal assessmentspersonal assessments.

How can personal assessments be subjected to critical evaluation?How can they produce a concept of probability of use to scientists and decision makers?How can they be measured—at all—or with enough accuracy to furnish appropriate numerical inputs for the probability calculus?

In the last sixty years logicians, mathematicians, and statisticians have made remarkable progress toward dealing with these questions.

Page 117: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

117

3-3c. Subjective Views (3/31)

The connection between beliefbelief, desiredesire, and actioaction is well known to psychologists and philosophers.

Illustrations: - If you believe your water supply has been poisonedwater supply has been poisoned,

you will resist attempts to make you drink from it even though you may be quite thirsty.

- If you cross a streetcross a street, we can reasonably infer that you want to get to the other side and believe it is safe to cross.

Frank Ramsey Frank Ramsey was the first theorist to use these connections to construct a subjective theory of probability.

Page 118: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

118

3-3c. Subjective Views (4/31)

Ramsey realized that our degrees of beliefdegrees of belief (or confidenceconfidence) in statements are connected with certain of our actions actions — the bets we make.

Ex: If you believe a certain horse is very likely to win a race, you are likely to accept a bet at less than even money. The more likely you think the horse is to win, the less favorable odds you will accept.

If we identify your personal probabilities by asking you asking you about the various odds you would acceptabout the various odds you would accept, we may be able to measure your personal probabilities.(Ramsey managed to parlay this into a full case for subjective probabilities.)

Page 119: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

119

3-3c. Subjective Views (5/31)

We are used to betting on the outcome of eventsoutcome of events, such as races, football games, or elections.But there is no reason in principle why we cannot bet on the truth of statements truth of statements too.For instance, instead of betting on Fancy Dancer to win in the third race, I can bet that the statement Fancy Dancer wins the third race is true.

If I am willing to set odds on enough statements set odds on enough statements and do so in a certain way, it can be shown that my odds constitute probability assignments to those statements and obey the probability calculus.

Page 120: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

120

3-3c. Subjective Views (6/31)

Bruno DeFinetti's proof:

- DeFinetti's reasoning deals with an agent an agent in a situation in which he must place a series of bets on a certain set of initial statementsinitial statements as well as all negationsnegations, conjunctionsconjunctions, disjunctionsdisjunctions, and conditional bets conditional bets that can be formed using these statements.

Ex: Suppose that you are the agent in question and the initial statements are — Jones will win the match. Smith will win the match. The crowd will be large.Then you will be expected to bet on those 3 statements and …

Page 121: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

121

3-3c. Subjective Views (7/31)

Bruno DeFinetti's proof:

Jones will not win the match. Smith will win the match or Jones will win the match.Jones will win the match and the crowd will notnot be large.

And conditional bets:Jones will win given that the crowd is large.Jones will not win given that the crowd is large and Smith does not win.

And so on, for all of the infinitely many bets that are constructible from the initial setconstructible from the initial set.

Page 122: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

122

3-3c. Subjective Views (8/31)

The set of statements on which the agent is expected to bet is called DeFinetti closure DeFinetti closure of the initial set of statements.

Given a set of statements A the DeFinetti closure of the DeFinetti closure of AA, DC(A)DC(A), may be formally defined as follows:

1. Every statement in A is also in DC(A). 2. If the statements S and W are in DC(A), so are the statements not Snot S, (S or W) (S or W) and (S&W)(S&W).3. If S and W are in DC(A), so is the phrase S given S given W. W. 4. Nothing is in DC(A) unless its being so follows from 1-3.

Page 123: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

123

3-3c. Subjective Views (9/31)

You are expected to place bets on every statementplace bets on every statement in the DeFinetti closure of your initial set with a "bookie".

- For you must post the odds on allall the statements and conditional bets in the DeFinetti closure, and that is all you are permitted to dothat is all you are permitted to do.

Once you set the odds, the the bookiebookie determines all determines all the other features of the betthe other features of the bet, includingthe amount at the amount at stakestake on the various bets and who bets who bets forfor or againstagainst a given statement.

Page 124: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

124

3-3c. Subjective Views (10/31)

A particular bet on a single statement p

- The entries under the statement p are simply the truth values. (true and false)

- The other entries tell how much you (or the bookie) win or lose for the various outcomes.

Ex: If you are betting for p and p is false, you "win“ -aS and the bookie wins aS.

p Payoff for p Payoff against p

T (1-a)S -(1-a)S

F -aS aS

Page 125: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

125

3-3c. Subjective Views (11/31)

A particular bet on a single statement p

- The entries in a row under "for" and "against" are the negatives of each other.

- SS is the stake for the bets(positive amount of money),aSaS and (1-a)S (1-a)S are portions of the stake, and aa is a number, called the betting quotient betting quotient for p,the ratio of a to 1-aratio of a to 1-a constitutes the oddsodds you set for the statement p. (Note that aS+(1-a)S=SaS+(1-a)S=S.)

p Payoff for p Payoff against p

T (1-a)S -(1-a)S

F -aS aS

Page 126: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

126

3-3c. Subjective Views (12/31)

A particular bet on a single statement p

- The higher you set the betting quotient a, the greater portion of the stake you risk losing;so, you will not set high odds for a statement unless you are quite confident confident it is true.

- The only feature you control is the odds a to 1-a. The bookie not only fixes the amount S at stakestake but also decides who is to be for pfor p and who is to be against pagainst p.

p Payoff for p Payoff against p

T (1-a)S -(1-a)S

F -aS aS

Page 127: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

127

3-3c. Subjective Views (13/31)

ExampleExample:Suppose the Golden Circle Race Track posts odds of 99 to 199 to 1 on Fancy Dancer to win.

This means that This means that —

- If the horse wins, the track will pay us $100 for every $1 "to win" ticket for that horse that we’ve purchased.

- The total stake for a $1 ticket is $100. We risk 1/100 of it, the track risks 99/100 of it.

In our terms In our terms the track's betting quotienttrack's betting quotient is 99/100, and the odds the odds are 99/100 to 1/100.

Page 128: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

128

3-3c. Subjective Views (14/31)

More generallyMore generally,

Someone offers odds of odds of a to b a to b on a given outcome.

Then they are willing to risk losing a portion a/(a+b) of a stake in case the outcome fails to obtain so long as we are willing to risk losing the portion b/(a+b) in case the outcome does obtain.

In our termsIn our terms — the odds are a/(a+b) to b/(a+b)a/(a+b) to b/(a+b) the betting quotient is a/(a+b)a/(a+b).

Page 129: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

129

3-3c. Subjective Views (15/31)

Returning to DeFinetti's work,

A clever bookie might be able to arrange the betsarrange the bets so that he was bound to have a net gain have a net gain no matter what happened.

Ex: Suppose you posted odds of 9/10 to 1/10 on a statement p and odds of 1/2 to 1/2 on its negation not p.

The bookie can force you to bet for p and for not p, and he fixes the stake at $1.

Page 130: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

130

3-3c. Subjective Views (16/31)

If p is trueIf p is true The bookie loses $.10 on his bet against p and wins $.50 on his bet against not p. That is a net gain of $.40. (You will have a net loss of $.40.)

pPayoff for p

Payoff against p

T 1/10 -1/10

F -9/10 9/10

Not pPayoff

for not pPayoff

against not p

T 5/10 -5/10

F -5/10 5/10

Page 131: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

131

3-3c. Subjective Views (17/31)

If p is falseIf p is false The bookie wins $.90 on his bet against p and loses $.50 on his bet against not p. Again, that is a net gain of $.40. (You will still have a net loss of $.40.)

The bookie has made a Dutch BookDutch Book against you.

pPayoff for p

Payoff against p

T 1/10 -1/10

F -9/10 9/10

Not pPayoff

for not pPayoff

against not p

T 5/10 -5/10

F -5/10 5/10

Page 132: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

132

3-3c. Subjective Views (18/31)

By posting odds of 1/10 to 9/10 on not pnot p or odds of 1/2 to 1/2 on pon p, or any other combination of odds under which your betting quotients for p and not p summed to your betting quotients for p and not p summed to 11, you could have protected yourself against this type of Dutch Book.

pPayoff for p

Payoff against p

T 5/10 -5/10

F -5/10 5/10

Not pPayoff

for not pPayoff

against not p

T 9/10 -9/10

F -1/10 1/10

pPayoff for p

Payoff against p

T 5/10 -5/10

F -5/10 5/10

Not pPayoff

for not pPayoff

against not p

T 9/10 -9/10

F -1/10 1/10

Page 133: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

133

3-3c. Subjective Views (19/31)

DUTCH BOOK THEOREMDUTCH BOOK THEOREM

Suppose that nono Dutch Book can be made Dutch Book can be made against an agent using the odds he posts on the DeFinetti closure of set of statements. Then his betting quotientsbetting quotients for the DeFinetti closure in question satisfy the probability calculussatisfy the probability calculus.

To establish the Dutch Book theorem, we will set P(p)= the agent's betting quotient for p = a

and verify that P(p)P(p) (i.e., aa) satisfies the axiomsaxioms of the probability calculus provided that no Dutch Book can be made against the agent.

Page 134: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

134

3-3c. Subjective Views (20/31)

To axiom laaxiom la, we must show that if no Dutch Book can be made against the agent, 0≤a≤1

(we will show in an indirect proof that if your betting quotients violate one of the axioms of the probability calculus, a Dutch Book can be made against you.)

Suppose Suppose that a<0,Then –a>0, (1-a)>1, and both the payoffs -aS and (1-a)S are positive.The bookie can guarantee himself a net gain by betting for pfor p at any positive stake S.Yours are negative, since you must bet against p.

Page 135: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

135

3-3c. Subjective Views (21/31)

On the other handOn the other hand, if a>1,then 1-a<0 and both -(1-a)S and aS are positive.So the bookie can make a Dutch Book against you by betting against pagainst p.His payoffs, being in the column under "Payoff against p", are bound to be positive.

p Payoff for p Payoff against p

T (1-a)S -(1-a)S

F -aS aS

Page 136: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

136

3-3c. Subjective Views (22/31)

To axiom 2axiom 2,Let us suppose that p is certainp is certain and show that if your betting quotient for p is less than 1, a Dutch Book can be made against you.(We have already established that it cannot be greater than 1.)

Since p is certain, we need only consider p is true.If a<1, then (1-a)S is positive; clearly the bookie can make a Dutch Book against you by betting for pfor p.

p Payoff for p Payoff against p

T (1-a)S -(1-a)S

Page 137: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

137

3-3c. Subjective Views (23/31)

To axiom 3axiom 3,Let aa be your betting quotient for p, bb the one for q and cc that for "p or q".(For simplicity, we have set the stakes at 1.)

p q

p q p or q

For Against For Against For Against

T T 1-a -(1-a) 1-b -(1-b) 1-c -(1-c)

T F 1-a -(1-a) -b b 1-c -(1-c)

F T -a a 1-b -(1-b) 1-c -(1-c)

F F -a a -b b -c c

Page 138: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

138

3-3c. Subjective Views (24/31)

Axiom 3 states that if p and q are mutually exclusive, P(p or q)=P(p)+P(q).

ThusThus we must show that we must show that if p and q are mutually exclusive and c≠a+b, a Dutch Book can be made against you.

- Assume that p and q are mutually exclusive.(This means the first row of betting table never applies and can be ignored.)

Also assume that c≠a+b, then either c<a+bc<a+b or c>a+bc>a+b.

Page 139: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

139

3-3c. Subjective Views (25/31)

- If c<a+b, (a+b)-c is positive.If the bookie bets : against pagainst p and against qagainst q but for "p or q"for "p or q"

In the 2nd row, he is paid -(1-a)+b+(1-c)=(a+b)-c 3rd row, a+[-(1-b)]+(1-c)=(a+b)-c 4th row, a+b+(-c)=(a+b)-c

his total payoffs for the last three rows of the table all equal (a+b)-c. (>0)

Thus the bookie can guarantee himself a positive net gain no matter what the truth values of p and q turn out to be.

Page 140: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

140

3-3c. Subjective Views (26/31)

- If c>a+b, c-(a+b) is positive.If the bookie bets : for pfor p and for qfor q but against "p or q"against "p or q"

In the 2nd row, he is paid (1-a)+(-b)+[-(1-c)]=c-(a+b) 3rd row, (-a)+(1-b)+[-(1-c)]=c-(a+b) 4th row, (-a)+(-b)+c=c-(a+b)

his total payoffs for the last three rows of the table all equal c-(a+b). (>0)

Thus the bookie can guarantee himself a positive net gain no matter what the truth values of p and q turn out to be.

Page 141: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

141

3-3c. Subjective Views (27/31)

Conditional bet: P(q|p)A bet on "q given p" as on only when only when pp is true is true, and then as won according to whether qq is true or false.

Using odds of odds of a to 1-a for the conditional bet "q given p", and payoffs of 00 to handle cases in which the bet is offthe bet is off..

p q For "q given p" Against "q given p"

T T 1-a -(1-a)

T F -a a

F T 0 0

F F 0 0

Page 142: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

142

3-3c. Subjective Views (28/31)

To axiom 1baxiom 1b.If a<0, the bookie can make a Dutch Book against you by betting forfor "q given p" "q given p".If a>1, the bookie can make a Dutch Book against you by betting againstagainst "q given p" "q given p".

Thus we know that axiom 1baxiom 1b must hold if we interpret "P(q|p)" as your betting quotient for "q given p".

p q For "q given p" Against "q given p"

T T 1-a -(1-a)

T F -a a

Page 143: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

143

3-3c. Subjective Views (29/31)

To axiom 4axiom 4.Assume your betting quotient for “p&q" is cc, that for p is aa, and that for "q given p" is bb.Axiom 4 states that P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q|pAxiom 4 states that P(p&q)=P(p)xP(q|p))

- We want to prove that We want to prove that if cc≠≠abab, a Dutch Book can be made against you.

p q

p q given p p & q

For Against For Against For Against

T T 1-a -(1-a) 1-b -(1-b) 1-c -(1-c)

T F 1-a -(1-a) -b b -c c

F T -a a 0 0 -c c

F F -a a 0 0 -c c

Page 144: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

144

3-3c. Subjective Views (30/31)

The bookie is free to choose the stake for each bet.

- Let us have the bookie set set the stake at b the stake at b for the betson p.

- Suppose cc≠≠abab, then c<ab or c>ab.

- If c<ab, ab-c is positive. So if the bookie bets againstagainst p p, againstagainst "q given p" "q given p", and forfor "p&q" "p&q", he will be paid ab-c no matter what.This means that he can make a Dutch Book against you.

p q

p

For Against

T T (1-a)b -(1-a)b

T F (1-a)b -(1-a)b

F T -ab ab

F F -ab ab

Page 145: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

145

3-3c. Subjective Views (31/31)

In the 1st row, -(1-a)b+[-(1-b)]+(1-c)=ab-cab-c 2nd row, -(1-a)b+b+(-c)=-b+ab+b-c=ab-cab-c 3rd and 4th row, ab+0+(-c)=ab-cab-c

- If c>ab, c-abc-ab is positive. So if the bookie bets forfor p p, forfor "q given p" "q given p", and againstagainst "p&q" "p&q", he will be paid c-ab no matter what.

In the 1st row, (1-a)b+(1-b)+[-(1-c)]=c-abc-ab 2nd row, (1-a)b+(-b)+c=b-ab-b+c=c-abc-ab 3rd and 4th row, -ab+0+c=c-abc-ab

This means that he can make a Dutch Book against you.

Page 146: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

146

3-3c. Problems Problems 1. Return to the Dutch Book argument for axiom 3 and complete the case for c>a+b that I left as an exercise. 2. Construct Dutch Book arguments to show that 0≤a≤1, where a is your betting quotient for "q given p."3. Carry out the check I asked you to make in the argument for axiom 4.4. Complete the argument for axiom 4 for the case when c>ab. 5. Give a Dutch Book argument to establish directly each of the following: a. If p is impossible, P(p)=0. b. P(p)+P(not p) =1. c. If p logically implies q, P(p)≤P(q).

Page 147: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

147

3-3d. 3-3d. CoherenceCoherence and Conditionalization and Conditionalization

Page 148: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

148

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(1/8)

DeFinetti called an agent's betting quotients coherentcoherent in case no Dutch Book can be made against him.

We can summarize DeFinetti's theorem :if an agent's subjective probabilities (betting quotients) are coherent,coherent, they obey the probability calculus.

If we accept coherence as a condition of rationality, DeFinetti's conclusion can be paraphrased asthe laws of probability are necessary conditions for the laws of probability are necessary conditions for rationalityrationality. .

Page 149: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

149

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(2/8)

Others have proved that having subjective probabilities that obey the probability calculus is also sufficient for coherence. i.e.,if an agent picks his betting quotients so as to satisfy the laws of probability, no Dutch Book can be made against him. (This is called thethe converse Dutch Book theorem converse Dutch Book theorem)

Page 150: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

150

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(3/8)

Rational people modify their degrees of belief modify their degrees of belief (subjective probabilities) (subjective probabilities) in the light of new datanew data.

ExEx: Whereas it would be reasonable for me to be quite confident that my spanking new car will not break down before I get it home, I would be much less confident about this if someone told me my new car was actually a "lemon“ that had just been returned to the dealer.

One very popular proposal for modifying subjective probabilities in the light of new data is that we use the rule of conditionalizationrule of conditionalization.

Page 151: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

151

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(4/8)

Rule of conditionalizationRule of conditionalization:

Suppose that DD is the conjunction of the statements describing the new data.

Then for each statement p, take PPNN(p)=P(p)=POO(p|D)(p|D). (Let the new probabilities be the old probabilities Let the new probabilities be the old probabilities conditional on the dataconditional on the data.)

Since P(D|D)=1, this rule has the effect of assigning the probability of 1 to the data.

If we replace "P(p)" with "P(p|D)P(p|D)" and "P(q|p)" with "P(qlp&D)P(qlp&D)" in every axiom of the probability calculusaxiom of the probability calculus, the formulas we obtain will be laws of probability too.

Page 152: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

152

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(5/8)

A reason favoring using conditionalization to change our probabilities, is that it guarantees the coherence guarantees the coherence of our new probabilitiesof our new probabilities.

There is also a Dutch Book argument supporting conditionalization.

SupposeSuppose you have revised the probability of D to 1, that of p to aa, and that your old P(p|D) was bb.

Now if aa≠≠bb, and if the bookie knows this in advanceif the bookie knows this in advance, he can make a Dutch Book against you.

Page 153: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

153

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(6/8)

He sets stake at $1. Before the truth of D is known, he places two betsplaces two bets:

one for pfor p—if a<b (or against p, if a>b);the other against "p given D"against "p given D"—if a<b (or for it, if a>b)

After D is verified, if a<b and p is true, his net is (1-a)+[-(1-b)]=b-a >0 p is false, his net is (-a)+b=b-a >0

pPayoff

for pPayoff

against p

T 1-a -(1-a)

F -a a

D p

p given D

For Against

T T 1-b -(1-b)

T F -b b

Page 154: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

154

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(7/8)

If D does not come true,the bookie neither gains nor loses since none of his bets are in effect. But he can assure himself of a gain even then by placing a side bet placing a side bet against Dagainst D.

Suppose that cc is your betting quotient for D anddd=|a-b|/2|a-b|/2, the bookie sets the stakestake on D at d/(1-c)d/(1-c).

If D is F, he is paid c[d/(1-c)]c[d/(1-c)] >0.If D is T, he is paid -(1-c)[d/(1-c)]=-d-d from the bet on D and (b-a)=2d2d from his other 2 bets, his net winnings are d >0.

DPayoff for D

Payoff against D

T (1-c)(d/1-c) -(1-c) (d/1-c)

F -c(d/1-c) c(d/1-c)

Page 155: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

155

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(8/8)

Summarization:Summarization:

- If an agent's subjective probability assignments are rationalrational in the sense of being coherentbeing coherent, then it follows, by the Dutch Book theorem, that they obey the laws of they obey the laws of the probability calculusthe probability calculus.

- By the converse Dutch Book theoremconverse Dutch Book theorem, obeying the laws of probabilitylaws of probability is sufficient for having coherentcoherent subjective probabilities.

- Using the rule of conditionalization rule of conditionalization will allow an agent to form new coherent probability assignmentsnew coherent probability assignments as he learns new data and will protect him against future Dutch Books.

Page 156: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

156

3-3d. Problems Problems

1. Show that we obtain a law of the probability calculus when P(plD) substituted for P(p) in axiom 1a.2. Do the same for axiom 2. 3. Do the same for axiom 3.

Page 157: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

157

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (1/15)

Have we made much of a case for the subjective approach?

Is not coherence such a loose requirement that probability assignments based on it are useless for scientists and decision makers?

If prior to a match race between a Kentucky Derby prospect and my old nag, I assign a 90%90% chance of winning to the old nag and a 10%10% chance to the racehorse, then I am coherentcoherent. Yet unless I know something very unusual about the race (such as that the racehorse has been given a horse-sized dosage of sleeping pills), I would be foolish to take bets at those odds.

Page 158: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

158

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (2/15)

This example suggests that coherence is not a coherence is not a strong enough requirement strong enough requirement for rationally assigning probabilities.

- There is a sense in which it would be irrational for me to set those odds on the old nag.

- - Since I know a fair bit about horses, I know that healthy young racehorses such as this one, participating in a normal match race against an old tired horse, are (virtually) certain to win.Given that, I should assign a probability of (nearly) 1 to the racehorse winning.

Page 159: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

159

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (3/15)

But what about those who know nothing about horses? (the subjectivist says:)

- First of all, they should bet coherently.

- Then they should try to learn more about the horses. As they acquire new information, they should modify their probability assignments. If they use conditionalization, they can be assured of preserving coherence.

The convergence theorems we mentioned in connection with Bayes's theorem may apply. If so, in the long run their odds are likely to be as good as those of the experts.

Page 160: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

160

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (4/15)

The convergence theoremsconvergence theorems show that a person can start with completely heretical heretical probability assignments, modify them by conditionalizingmodify them by conditionalizing, and be assured in the long run of convergingconverging to the probabilities used by the experts.

(Subjectivists appeal to this to argue that subjective probabilities are suitable for scientists and decision makers.)

Subjectivists can assign probabilities where frequencies, propensities, or logically based measures are unavailable or in principle unattainable.

Page 161: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

161

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (5/15)

The capstone of the subjectivist defense consists in noting that subjective elements intrude in the ascertainment of so-called objective probabilities too.

- Under the classical view, we must choose the "equiprobable" possibilities "equiprobable" possibilities to assign to a statement. This choice is based on a personal and subjective personal and subjective judgment judgment that we have the right set of possibilities and that they are equiprobableequiprobable, since the classical view fails to supply any methods for associating a set of equiprobable possibilities with a given statement.

Page 162: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

162

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (6/15)

- Similarly, when we decide,after seeing a coin land heads on 511 of 1,000 tosses, that the long-run relative frequency of heads is 1/2, we are making a personal assessment a personal assessment of the probable the probable future behavior future behavior of the coin.

The application of objective probabilities is dependent on subjective ones. Subjective probabilities are thus both fundamental and unavoidable.

Page 163: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

163

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (7/15)

The subjective approach faces some problems of its some problems of its ownown:

- Subjectivists' assurances about long-run convergence long-run convergence may fail to work out in practice.If the initial probabilities are widely divergent divergent and the data either sparse or inconclusivedata either sparse or inconclusive, convergence may not come until long after a decision based on the probabilities in question is due.

- There is a plethora of statements for which we can set betting quotients betting quotients at values that do not comply with the probability calculus without having to worry about being trapped in a Dutch Book.

Page 164: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

164

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (8/15)

Ex: A bet on whether the heat death of the universe the heat death of the universe will ever occur.

If it does occur, no one will be around to be paid; if it is not going to occur, we might not know that with enough certainty to settle the bet.

Ex: A bet on whether there is life outside life outside the observable portion of the universe.

Subjectivists might respond: "Can't we settle those bets by appealing to science?“Here we cannot.Science has no definite answers no definite answers to these questions; it tells us only that each of the outcomes is possible.

Page 165: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

165

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization (9/15)

A related problem:

The betting approach presumes that once we make a bet it will remain clear what winning means remain clear what winning means until the bet is settled. But that it not always sonot always so.

- FrequentlyFrequently, we find ourselves in situations where we initiallyinitially wonder whether something is true and thenthen find that our very question does not really make does not really make sensesense or fails to have a definite answerfails to have a definite answer.

Page 166: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

166

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(10/15)

ExampleExample : SupposeSuppose that you bet that the fellow in the corner drinking gin gin knows how to play bridge andI bet that he does not.Next suppose Next suppose we learn that no one in that corner is drinking gin, although one of the men is drinking vodkavodka—and he does play bridge. Is our bet still on? Is our bet still on? You say it is and claim that it was clear that we meant that fellow—the one over there. I say that it is not and that I meant the gin drinker, since I would never bet on a vodka drinker's being able to play bridge.

Page 167: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

167

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(11/15)

If we turn to the history of science and mathematics, we can even find cases where our conception of what counts as an "answeranswer" to a question changed in changed in the course of finding onethe course of finding one.

We can no more count on the subjective approach to be universally applicable.

Page 168: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

168

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(12/15)

Subjectivists face a difficult dilemma difficult dilemma concerning the revision of probabilities.

ExEx: Suppose I, who know nothing of abstract art, have become friendly with some art critics and start to visit museums of modern art with them.I know what I like, but I try to guess at what the critics like. At firstAt first, I use my best hunches best hunches to assign probabilities to their liking various paintings and other art objects, being sure, of course, to be coherentto be coherent. LaterLater, when I learn what the critics have to say, I see that my probabilities must be modifiedmodified. How should I do this?How should I do this?

Page 169: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

169

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(13/15)

- To use the rule of conditionalizationthe rule of conditionalization.But, suppose, I find that that rule yields probabilities that are still far from those I am now inclined to hold. What should I do? What should I do? Stick with the rule and hope that convergence will soon come?Or give up my initial priors and start with a new set?

-> -> The challenge for the subjectivist is to propose a middle coursemiddle course, that is, a rational method a rational method for the modification of probabilities that is wedded to neitherneither unwarranted tenacity nor flippancytenacity nor flippancy.

Page 170: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

170

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(14/15)

Solutions to this problem have been proposed.

They have been tied to the abandonment abandonment of a unique prior probability assignment in favor of sets of assignments sets of assignments or intervals between intervals between upper and lower probabilitiesupper and lower probabilities.

This amounts to rejecting the original subjectivist rejecting the original subjectivist viewview—at least in its full particulars.

Page 171: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

171

3-3d.Coherence and Conditionalization(15/15)

No decision No decision as to which conception is best. However, at least you should have a clear

idea of the difficultiesdifficulties a successful view must overcome and of the advantages advantages and drawbacksdrawbacks to the major views that have been proposed so far.

Page 172: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

172

3-4. References3-4. References

Page 173: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

173

3-4. ReferencesSkyrms 1975 contains a good introduction to probability theory and the interpretations of probability. Chernoff and Moses expound somewhat more advanced material. Raiffa presents an excellent discussion of the use of Bayes's theorem in decision theory as well as an introduction to subjective probability. Carnap is a classic on the logical and philosophical foundations of probability. The papers by DeFinetti and Ramsey are reprinted in Kyburg and Smokier. Also see Savage and Eells for defenses of the subjective approach. Kyburg presents an account of probability that fails to obey the entire probability calculus; it also contains a number of critical papers on the various interpretations of probability as well as further references. See Levi for another novel approach and further criticism of standard Bayesianism.

Page 174: 1 DECISIONS UNDER RISK: PROBABILITY 指導老師 : 梁德昭 老師 報告者 : 曾阿玉 日 期 : 2009 年 10 月 26 日

174

The EndThe EndThanks for your attentionThanks for your attention