stiglitz. globalization and its discontents 1

30
Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents Page 1 of 14 Volume 49, Number 13 · August 15, 2002 Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents by Joseph E. Stiglitz Norton, 282 pp., $24.95 1. The most pressing economic problem of our time is that so many of what we usually call "developing economies" are, in fact, not developing. It is shocking to most citizens of the industrialized Western democracies to realize that in Uganda, or Ethiopia, or Malawi, neither men nor women can expect to live even to age forty‐ five. Or that in Sierra Leone 28 percent of all children die before reaching their fifth birthday. Or that in India more than half of all children are malnourished. Or that in Bangladesh just half of the adult men, and fewer than one fourth of adult women, can read and write. [1] What is more troubling still, however, is to realize that many if not most of the world's poorest countries, where very low incomes and incompetent governments combine to create such appalling human tragedy, are making no progress—at least not on the economic front. Of the fifty countries where per capita incomes were lowest in 1990 (on average, just $1,450 per annum in today's US dollars, even after we allow for the huge differences in the cost of living in those countries and in the US), twenty‐three had lower average incomes in 1999 than they did in 1990. And of the twenty‐seven that managed to achieve at least some positive growth, the average rate of increase was only 2.7 percent per annum. At that rate it will take them another seventy‐nine years to reach the income level now enjoyed by Greece, the poorest member of the European Union. [2] This sorry situation stands in sharp contrast to the buoyant optimism, both economic and political, of the early postwar period. The economic historian Alexander Gerschenkron's classic essay "Economic Backwardness in Historical Perspective" suggested that countries that were far behind the technological frontier of their day enjoyed a great advantage: they could simply imitate what had already proved successful elsewhere, without having to assume either the costs or the risks of innovating on their own. The economist and demographer Simon Kuznets, who went on to win a Nobel Prize, observed that economic inequalities

Upload: arab

Post on 22-Nov-2014

253 views

Category:

Documents


4 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 1 of 14

Volume 49, Number 13 · August 15, 2002 

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case 

By Benjamin M. Friedman 

Globalization and Its Discontents 

by Joseph E. Stiglitz 

Norton, 282 pp., $24.95 

1. 

The most pressing economic problem of our time is that so many of what we usually call  "developing  economies"  are,  in  fact,  not  developing.  It  is  shocking  to  most citizens  of  the  industrialized  Western  democracies  to  realize  that  in  Uganda,  or Ethiopia, or Malawi, neither men nor women can expect  to  live even  to age  forty‐five. Or that in Sierra Leone 28 percent of all children die before reaching their fifth birthday. Or that in India more than half of all children are malnourished. Or that in Bangladesh  just half of  the adult men, and  fewer  than one  fourth of adult women, can read and write.[1]  

What  is  more  troubling  still,  however,  is  to  realize  that  many  if  not  most  of  the world's poorest countries, where very  low incomes and  incompetent governments combine to create such appalling human tragedy, are making no progress—at least not  on  the  economic  front.  Of  the  fifty  countries  where  per  capita  incomes  were lowest in 1990 (on average, just $1,450 per annum in today's US dollars, even after we allow for the huge differences in the cost of living in those countries and in the US), twenty‐three had lower average incomes in 1999 than they did in 1990. And of the  twenty‐seven  that  managed  to  achieve  at  least  some  positive  growth,  the average  rate of  increase was only 2.7 percent per  annum. At  that  rate  it will  take them another seventy‐nine years to reach the income level now enjoyed by Greece, the poorest member of the European Union.[2]  

 

This  sorry  situation  stands  in  sharp  contrast  to  the  buoyant  optimism,  both economic  and  political,  of  the  early  postwar  period.  The  economic  historian Alexander  Gerschenkron's  classic  essay  "Economic  Backwardness  in  Historical Perspective"  suggested  that  countries  that  were  far  behind  the  technological frontier of their day enjoyed a great advantage: they could simply imitate what had already proved successful elsewhere, without having to assume either the costs or the  risks  of  innovating  on  their  own.  The  economist  and  demographer  Simon Kuznets,  who went  on  to win  a  Nobel  Prize,  observed  that  economic  inequalities 

Page 2: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 2 of 14

often widen when a country first begins to industrialize, but argued that they then narrow again as development proceeds. Albert Hirschman, an economist and social thinker, put forward the hypothesis that, for a while, at the beginning of a country's economic development, the tolerance of its citizens for inequality increases, so that the temporary widening that troubled Kuznets need not be an insuperable obstacle. Throughout the countries that had been colonies of the great European empires, the view of  the departing powers was  that  the newly  installed democratic  institutions and  forms  they  were  leaving  behind  would  follow  the  path  of  the  Western democracies.  Political  alliances,  like  the myriad  regional  pacts  established  during the Eisenhower‐Dulles era (SEATO, CENTO, and all the others), would help cement these gains in place.  

Not  surprisingly,  the  contrast  between  that  earlier  heady  optimism  and  today's grimmer reality has led to a serious (and increasingly acrimonious) debate over two closely  related  questions.  What,  in  retrospect,  has  caused  the  failure  of  so  many countries to achieve the advances confidently predicted for them a generation ago? And what should they, and those abroad who sympathize with their plight and seek to help, do now?  

 

Perhaps  not  since  the worldwide depression  of  the  1930s  have  so many  thinkers attacked  a  problem  from  such  different  perspectives:  Have  the  non‐developing economies  (to  call  them  that) pursued  the wrong domestic policies? Or have  they been innocent victims of exploitation by the industrialized world? Is it futile to try to foster  economic  development  without  an  appropriate  social  and  political infrastructure,  including what has come to be called the "rule of  law" and perhaps also  including  political  democracy  as  well?  Or  do  these  favorable  institutional creations follow only after a sustained improvement in material standards of living is already underway? Would more foreign aid help? Or does direct assistance from abroad  only  create  parallels  on  a  national  scale  to  the  "welfare  dependency" sometimes  alleged  in  the  US,  dulling  the  incentive  for  countries  to  undertake difficult  but  needed  reforms?  How  much  blame  lies  with  corruption  in  the nondeveloping  countries'  governments,  often  including  the  outright  theft  by government officials of a large fraction of whatever aid is received? And then there is  the  most  controversial  question  of  all:  Is  the  "culture"  of  these  countries—specifically  in  contrast  to  Western  culture—simply  not  conducive  to  economic success? 

One  important  concrete  expression  of  the  optimism  with  which  thinking  in  the industrialized world addressed the challenge of economic development a generation and more ago, before these painful questions became prominent, was the creation of new  multinational  institutions  to  further  various  aspects  of  the  broader development  goal.  The United Nations  spawned  a  family  of  sub‐units  to  this  end, most prominently  the UN Development Program and  the UN Conference on Trade and  Development.  The  Food  and  Agriculture  Organization  (founded  in  1945,  but 

Page 3: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 3 of 14

separately  from  the  UN)  and  the  World  Health  Organization  (1948)  had  more specific  mandates.  The  International  Bank  for  Reconstruction  and  Development (commonly called the World Bank), established in 1944 mostly to help rebuild war‐torn Europe, soon shifted  its attention to  the developing world once that  task was largely completed.  

The  International  Monetary  Fund  (the  IMF,  or  sometimes  just  the  Fund)  was  a latecomer to the development field. Established in tandem with the World Bank in 1944, the IMF's original mission was to preserve stability in international financial markets  by  helping  countries  both  to  make  economic  adjustments  when  they encountered an  imbalance of  international payments and  to maintain  the value of their  currency  in what  everyone  assumed would  be  a  permanent  regime  of  fixed exchange rates. 

By the early 1970s, however, the fixed exchange rate system proved untenable, and floating  rates of one kind or another became  the norm. Moreover, as  the Western European  economies  gained  strength  while,  at  the  same  time,  more  and  more developing  countries  entered  the  international  trading  and  financial  economy,  it was  increasingly  the  developing  countries  that  ran  into  balance  of  payments problems or  difficulties  over  their  currencies  and  therefore  turned  to  the  IMF  for assistance.  As  a  result,  over  time  the  IMF  became  increasingly  involved  in  the business  of  economic  development.  And  as  development  has  faltered  in  many countries—including  many  in  which  the  IMF  has  played  a  significant  part—the IMF's  policies  and  actions  have  increasingly  moved  to  the  center  of  an  ongoing, intense debate over who or what to blame for the failures of the past and what to do differently in the future. 

Joseph E. Stiglitz, in Globalization and Its Discontents, offers his views both of what has gone wrong and of what to do differently. But the main focus of his book is who to blame. According to Stiglitz,  the story of  failed development does have a villain, and the villain is truly detestable: the villain is the IMF. 

2. 

Joseph Stiglitz  is  a Nobel Prize–winning  economist,  and he deserves  to be. Over  a long career, he has made incisive and highly valued contributions to the explanation of  an  astonishingly broad  range of  economic phenomena,  including  taxes,  interest rates, consumer behavior, corporate finance, and much else. Especially among econ‐omists who are still of active working age, he ranks as a titan of the field. In recent years Stiglitz has also been an active participant in economic policymaking, first as a member  and  then  as  chairman  of  the  US  Council  of  Economic  Advisers  (in  the Clinton  administration),  and  then,  from  1997  to  2000,  as  chief  economist  of  the World  Bank.  As  the  numerous  examples  and  personal  recollections  in  this  book make clear, his information and his impressions are in many cases firsthand. 

Page 4: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 4 of 14

In  Globalization  and  Its  Discontents  Stiglitz  bases  his  argument  for  different economic policies squarely on the themes that his decades of theoretical work have emphasized:  namely,  what  happens  when  people  lack  the  key  information  that bears on the decisions they have to make, or when markets for important kinds of transactions are inadequate or don't exist, or when other institutions that standard economic thinking takes for granted are absent or flawed. 

The implication of each of these absences or flaws is that free markets, left to their own devices, do not necessarily deliver the positive outcomes claimed for them by textbook  economic  reasoning  that  assumes  that  people  have  full  information,  can trade  in  complete  and  efficient markets,  and  can depend on  satisfactory  legal  and other  institutions.  As  Stiglitz  nicely  puts  the  point,  "Recent  advances  in  economic theory"—he  is  in  part  referring  to  his  own  work—"have  shown  that  whenever information  is  imperfect  and  markets  incomplete,  which  is  to  say  always,  and especially in developing countries, then the invisible hand works most imperfectly."  

As a result, Stiglitz continues, governments can improve the outcome by well‐chosen interventions. (Whether any given government will actually choose its interventions well is another matter.) At the level of national economies, when families and firms seek to buy too little compared to what the economy can produce, governments can fight recessions and depressions by using expansionary monetary and fiscal policies to  spur  the  demand  for  goods  and  services.  At  the  microeconomic  level, governments  can  regulate  banks  and  other  financial  institutions  to  keep  them sound.  They  can  also  use  tax  policy  to  steer  investment  into  more  productive industries and trade policies to allow new industries to mature to the point at which they can survive foreign competition. And governments can use a variety of devices, ranging  from  job  creation  to  manpower  training  to  welfare  assistance,  to  put unemployed labor back to work and, at the same time, cushion the human hardship deriving  from  what—importantly,  according  to  the  theory  of  incomplete information, or markets, or institutions—is no one's fault. 

Stiglitz  complains  that  the  IMF  has  done  great  damage  through  the  economic policies  it  has  prescribed  that  countries  must  follow  in  order  to  qualify  for  IMF loans, or for loans from banks and other private‐sector lenders that look to the IMF to indicate whether a borrower is creditworthy. The organization and its officials, he argues,  have  ignored  the  implications  of  incomplete  information,  inadequate markets, and unworkable  institutions—all of which are especially characteristic of newly developing countries. As a result, Stiglitz argues, time and again the IMF has called for policies that conform to textbook economics but do not make sense for the countries  to which the  IMF  is  recommending  them. Stiglitz seeks  to show that  the consequences of  these misguided policies have been disastrous, not  just according to  abstract  statistical measures  but  in  real  human  suffering,  in  the  countries  that have followed them.  

 

Page 5: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 5 of 14

Most of the specific policies that Stiglitz criticizes will be familiar to anyone who has paid even modest attention to the recent economic turmoil in the developing world (which  for  this  purpose  includes  the  former  Soviet  Union  and  the  former  Soviet satellite countries that are now unwinding their decades of Communist misrule): 

Fiscal  austerity.  The  most  traditional  and  perhaps  best‐known  IMF  policy recommendation is for a country to cut government spending or raise taxes, or both, to balance its budget and eliminate the need for government borrowing. The usual underlying  presumption  is  that  much  government  spending  is  wasteful  anyway. Stiglitz  charges  that  the  IMF  has  reverted  to  Herbert  Hoover's  economics  in imposing  these  policies  on  countries  during  deep  recessions,  when  the  deficit  is mostly the result of an induced decline in revenues; he argues that cuts in spending or tax hikes only make the downturn worse. He also emphasizes the social cost of cutting  back  on  various  kinds  of  government  programs—for  example,  eliminating food subsidies for the poor, which Indonesia did at the IMF's behest in 1998, only to be engulfed by food riots. 

High interest rates. Many countries come to the IMF because they are having trouble maintaining  the  exchange  value  of  their  currencies.  A  standard  IMF recommendation  is  high  interest  rates,  which  make  deposits  and  other  assets denominated  in  the  currency more  attractive  to  hold.  Rapidly  increasing  prices—sometimes at the hyperinflation level—are also a familiar problem in the developing world, and tight monetary policy,  implemented mostly through high interest rates, is again the standard corrective. Stiglitz argues that the high interest rates imposed on many countries by the IMF have worsened their economic downturns. They are intended  to  fight  inflation  that was not a  serious problem  to begin with;  and  they have forced the bankruptcy of countless otherwise productive companies that could not meet the suddenly increased cost of servicing their debts. 

Trade  liberalization.  Everyone  favors  free  trade—except many  of  the  people who make things and sell them. Eliminating tariffs, quotas, subsidies, and other barriers to free trade usually has little to do directly with what has driven a country to seek an IMF loan; but the IMF usually recommends (in effect, requires) eliminating such barriers as a condition  for  receiving credit. The argument  is  the usual one,  that  in the long run free trade practiced by everyone benefits everyone: each country will arrive at the mixture of products that it can sell competitively by using its resources and skills efficiently. Stiglitz points out that today's industrialized countries did not practice free trade when they were first developing, and that even today they do so highly  imperfectly.  (Witness  this year's  increase  in agricultural  subsidies and new barriers  to  steel  imports  in  the  US.)  He  argues  that  forcing  today's  developing countries  to  liberalize  their  trade  before  they  are  ready  mostly  wipes  out  their domestic industry, which is not yet ready to compete. 

Liberalizing Capital Markets. Many developing countries have weak banking systems and  few  opportunities  for  their  citizens  to  save  in  other  ways.  As  one  of  the conditions for extending a  loan,  the IMF often requires that  the country's  financial 

Page 6: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 6 of 14

markets be open to participation by foreign‐owned institutions. The rationale is that foreign banks are sounder, and that they and other foreign investment firms will do a better  job of mobilizing and allocating  the  country's  savings.  Stiglitz  argues  that the  larger  and more  efficient  foreign  banks drive  the  local  banks  out  of  business; that  the  foreign  institutions  are  much  less  interested  in  lending  to  the  country's domestically  owned  businesses  (except  to  the  very  largest  of  them);  and  that mobilizing  savings  is  not  a  problem because many  developing  countries  have  the highest savings rates in the world anyway. 

Privatization.  Selling  off  government‐  owned  enterprises—telephone  companies, railroads,  steel producers,  and many more—has been a major  initiative of  the  last two decades  both  in  industrialized  countries  and  in  some parts  of  the  developing world. One reason for doing so is the expectation that private management will do a better  job  of  running  these  activities.  Another  is  that  many  of  these  public companies should not be running at all, and only the government's desire to provide welfare disguised as jobs, or worse yet the opportunity for graft, keeps them going. Especially when  countries  that  come  to  the  IMF have  a  budget  deficit,  a  standard recommendation nowadays is to sell public‐sector companies to private investors.  

Stiglitz  argues  that  many  of  these  countries  do  not  yet  have  financial  systems capable of handling such transactions, or regulatory systems capable of preventing harmful behavior once the firms are privatized, or systems of corporate governance capable of monitoring the new managements. Especially in Russia and other parts of the former Soviet Union, he says, the result of premature privatization has been to give away the nation's assets to what amounts to a new criminal class.  

Fear of default.  A  top priority  of  IMF policy,  from  the very beginning,  has been  to maintain wherever possible the fiction that countries do not default on their debts. As a formal matter, the IMF always gets repaid. And when banks can't collect what they're owed, they typically accept a "voluntary" restructuring of the country's debt. The problem with all this, Stiglitz argues, is that the new credit that the IMF extends, in order to avoid the appearance of default, often serves only to take off the hook the banks and other private lenders that have accepted high risk in exchange for a high return for  lending to these countries  in  the first place. They want, he writes,  to be rescued  from  the  consequences  of  their  own  reckless  credit  policies.  Stiglitz  also argues  that  the  end  result  is  to  saddle  a  developing  country's  taxpayers with  the permanent burden of  paying  interest  and principal  on  the new debts  that  pay  off yesterday's mistakes. 

 

Stiglitz's indictment of the IMF and its policies is more than just an itemized bill of particulars. His theme is  that  there  is a coherence to this set of  individual policies, that  the  failings of which he accuses  the  IMF are not  just  random mistakes.  In his view  these  policies—what  he  labels  the  "Washington  consensus"—add  up  to something that is unattractive, if not outright repugnant, in several different ways.  

Page 7: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 7 of 14

First,  Stiglitz  repeatedly  claims  that  the  IMF's  policies  stem  not  from  economic analysis  and  observation  but  from  ideology—specifically,  an  ideological commitment to free markets and a concomitant antipathy to government. Again and again he accuses  IMF officials of deliberately  ignoring  the "facts on the ground"  in the countries to which they were offering recommendations. In part his complaint is that  they  did  not  understand,  or  at  least  did  not  take  into  account,  his  and  other economists'  theoretical work  showing  that  unfettered markets  do  not  necessarily deliver  positive  results  when  information  or  market  structures  or  institutional infrastructure are incomplete.  

More specifically, he argues that the IMF ignores the need for proper "sequencing." Liberalizing  a  country's  trade  makes  sense  when  its  industries  have  matured sufficiently  to  reach  a  competitive  level,  but  not  before.  Privatizing  government‐owned  firms  makes  sense  when  adequate  regulatory  systems  and  corporate governance  laws  are  in  place,  but  not  before.  The  IMF,  he  argues,  deliberately ignores such factors, instead adopting a "cookie cutter" approach in which one set of policies  is  right  for  all  countries  regardless  of  their  individual  circumstances.  But importantly,  in  his  eyes,  the  underlying  motivation  is  ideological:  a  belief  in  the superiority of free markets that he sees as, in effect, a form of religion, impervious to either counterarguments or counterevidence. 

A  further  implication  of  this  belief  in  the  efficacy  of  free  markets,  according  to Stiglitz,  is  that  the  IMF  has  abandoned  its  original  Keynesian  mission  of  helping countries to maintain full employment while they make the adjustments they need in  their balances of payments;  instead  the  IMF recommends policies  that  result  in steeper downturns and more widespread joblessness. He does not argue, of course, that  the  IMF prefers  serious  recessions or unemployment per  se. Rather  it  simply acts on the belief—seriously mistaken in his view—that allowing free markets to do their work will automatically  take care of  such problems. By extension, he argues, the IMF also does not act to promote economic growth (which helps to produce full employment). Again the claim is not that the IMF dislikes growth per se, but that it believes free markets are all that is needed to make growth happen. 

As  a  further  consequence  of  the misguided policies  that  follow  from  this  "curious blend of  ideology and bad economics," Stiglitz argues,  the  IMF itself  is responsible for worsening—in  some cases,  for  actually  creating—the problems  it  claims  to be fighting.  By  making  countries  maintain  overvalued  exchange  rates  that  everyone knows will have to fall sooner or later, the IMF gives currency traders a one‐way bet and  therefore  encourages  market  speculation.  By  forcing  countries  that  are  in trouble  to  slash  their  imports,  the  IMF  encourages  the  contagion  of  an  economic downturn  from  one  country  to  its  neighbors.  By  making  countries  adopt  high interest  rates  that  stifle  investment  and bankrupt  companies,  the  IMF  encourages low  confidence  on  the  part  of  foreign  lenders.  At  the  same  time,  by  repeatedly coming to these lenders' rescue, the IMF encourages lax credit standards. 

 

Page 8: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 8 of 14

Second,  and  more  darkly,  the  IMF,  in  Stiglitz's  view,  systematically  acts  in  the interest  of  creditors,  and  of  rich  elites  more  generally,  in  preference  to  that  of workers,  peasants,  and  other  poor  people.  He  sees  it  as  no  accident  that  the  IMF regularly provides money that goes to pay off loans made by banks and bondholders who are eager to accept the high interest rates that go along with assuming risk—while preaching the virtues of free markets as they do so—although they are equally eager to be rescued by governments and the IMF when risk turns into reality.  

Stiglitz  also  thinks  it  is  no  coincidence  that  food  subsidies  and  other  ways  of cushioning the hardships suffered by the poor are among the first programs that the IMF tells countries to cut when they need to balance their budgets. He observes that IMF officials tend to meet only with finance ministers and central bank governors, as well as with bankers and investment bankers; they never meet with poor peasants or  unemployed workers.  He  also  notes  that many  IMF  officials  come  to  the  Fund from jobs in the private financial sector, while others, after working at the IMF, go on to take jobs at banks or other financial firms. 

Here  again  Stiglitz's  point  is  that  the  IMF's  mistakes  are  not  random  but  the systematic  consequence of  its  fundamental biases. His argument  is as much about the policies the IMF doesn't recommend as the ones it does:  

Stabilization  is on  the agenda;  job creation  is off. Taxation, and  its adverse effects, are on the agenda; land reform is off. There is money to bail out banks but not to pay for  improved education and health services,  let alone  to bail out workers who are thrown out of their jobs as a result of the IMF's macroeconomic mismanagement. 

One  specific  example,  land  reform,  sharply  illustrates  what  he  has  in  mind.  As Stiglitz points out, in many developing countries a small group of families own much of  the  cultivated  land.  Agriculture  is  organized  according  to  sharecropping,  with tenant farmers keeping perhaps half, or less, of what they produce. Stiglitz argues,  

The sharecropping system weakens incentives—where they share equally with the landowners, the effects are the same as a 50 percent tax on poor farmers. The IMF rails against high tax rates that are imposed against the rich, pointing out how they destroy  incentives,  but  nary  a  word  is  spoken  about  these  hidden  taxes....  Land reform represents a fundamental change in the structure of society, one that those in the elite that populates the finance ministries, those with whom the international finance institutions interact, do not necessarily like.  

Stiglitz considers, and rejects, the view that these and other choices are the result of a  conspiracy  between  the  IMF  and  powerful  interests  in  the  richer  countries—a view that is increasingly popular among the anti‐globalization protesters who now appear at the IMF's (and the World Bank's) meetings. Stiglitz's view is that in recent decades  the  IMF  "was  not  participating  in  a  conspiracy,  but  it  was  reflecting  the interests and ideology of the Western financial community."  

Page 9: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 9 of 14

Finally,  Stiglitz  sees  the  IMF's  systematic  biases  as  a  reflection  of  a  deeper moral failing:  

The  lack of concern about the poor was not  just a matter of views of markets and government,  views  that  said  that  markets  would  take  care  of  everything  and government would only make matters worse; it was also a matter of values.... While misguidedly working to preserve what it saw as the sanctity of the credit contract, the IMF was willing to tear apart the even more important social contract.  

Throughout the book, the sense of moral outrage is evident. 

3. 

Do Stiglitz's criticisms hold up? 

To  begin,  it  is  easy  enough  to  accuse  Stiglitz  of  selective  memory.  From  reading Globalization and Its Discontents, one would never know that the IMF had ever done anything useful. Or that Stiglitz, and his colleagues first at the Council of Economic Advisers and then at the World Bank, had ever gotten anything wrong. Or that those against whom he often  argued  in  the US  government—especially  at  the Treasury, which he continually portrays as complicit in the IMF's misdeeds, but at the Federal Reserve System too—had ever gotten a question right. (In the book's sole mention of Alan Greenspan, Stiglitz accuses him of being excessively concerned with inflation to  the exclusion of a vigorous expansion  that  could have otherwise  taken place  in the US during the Clinton years.)  

One can also disagree with Stiglitz over  the consequences of what  the  IMF plainly did,  even  including  those  policies  it  pursued  that most  people  now  agree  proved counterproductive. By 2002 the Asian financial crisis of 1997–1998 is receding into the past. While some of  the affected countries (most obviously  Indonesia) still  feel its effects, by now others have made solid recoveries. Stiglitz is right that they have not  regained,  and probably will  not,  the  rates  of  growth  they  achieved before  the crisis. But those rapid growth rates may well have been unsustainable in any case. Even in Russia, where per capita income remains well below what it was when the Soviet  Union  collapsed,  and  where  the  IMF  pursued  the  policies  toward  which Stiglitz  is  the most  scathing,  the  economic  situation  looks better  today  than  it  did when he was writing his book. 

A more  fundamental  problem,  as  Stiglitz  readily  acknowledges,  is  that we  cannot reliably  know  whether  the  consequences  of  the  IMF's  policies  were  worse  than whatever  the  alternative  would  have  been.  Many  longtime  observers  of  the developing world will notice that Stiglitz rarely mentions economic policy mistakes that poor countries make on their own initiative. Nor does he pay much attention to the  large‐scale corruption  that  is endemic  in many developing economies—except in the case of corruption in Russia, where he argues that the privatization program 

Page 10: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 10 of 14

pushed by the IMF opened the way for corruption on a historically unprecedented scale. He also never points out that the typical developing country spends far more on  its military  forces  (to  fight whom?)  than  it  receives  in  foreign aid; yet  it would seem necessary to take account of such wasteful expenditures, along with graft in all its  forms,  if one is  to give a clear picture of why the nondeveloping economies are not succeeding. 

It  is  surprising  too,  in  light of his emphasis on  the absence of adequate regulation and supervision of  financial  institutions  in  the developing world,  that Stiglitz does not  make more  of  the  mistakes made  by  private‐sector  businesses.  For  example, what made Korea vulnerable to the 1997–1998 Asian turmoil was that the country's business  conglomerates  (the  "chaebols")  had  borrowed  too  heavily,  and  that  the country's banks had financed these loans by borrowing in US dollars and relending in Korean won. True, banks abroad that were lending in dollars to the Korean banks may have become excessively confident that the IMF would bail them out if anything went wrong.  But  surely much of  the  fault  lay with Korea's  own businessmen  and bankers. And once they had built their house of cards, how much damage would its inevitable collapse have caused if the IMF had simply stayed away? 

Defenders of  the  IMF cannot claim  that all went well after  countries  implemented the Fund's recommendations. But they would presumably argue that events would have  turned  out  even  worse  on  some  alternative  course.  They  would  also presumably  argue  that  of  course  they  knew  that  information  was  imperfect,  and markets  incomplete, and institutions absent,  in the countries that came to the IMF for assistance. The issue, to be argued on a case‐by‐case basis, is just what different set of actions might therefore have proved more beneficial. 

 

Interestingly, there is also disagreement today over just how prevalent dire poverty is  in  the  developing  world—and,  what  is  more  important,  whether  poverty  is increasing  or  decreasing.  Stiglitz  echoes  the  standard  view  that  the  number  of people  around  the world  living  on  less  than  $1  per  day,  or  $2  per  day,  has  been increasing  in  recent  years.  By  contrast,  his  own  colleague  in  the  Columbia Economics Department, Xavier Sala‐i‐Martin, has recently published a study arguing just  the opposite.[3]  Sala‐i‐Martin's point  is  that  for purposes of assessing whether someone  is  economically well  off or miserable, what matters  is not how many US dollars  the  person's  income  could  buy  in  the  foreign  exchange  market  but  what standard  of  living  that  income  can  support  in  the  place  where  he  or  she  lives. Because the currency values established in foreign exchange markets (and also the values that governments set officially  for currencies  for which there  is no market) often  do  not  accurately  reflect  purchasing  power,  the  difference between  the  two measures of income is sometimes large.  

In India, for example, the average person's income in rupees in 2000 translated into just $460 per year at  the prevailing market exchange rate of 44 rupees per dollar. 

Page 11: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 11 of 14

But  because  food,  clothing,  housing,  and  other  consumer  necessities  are  so much cheaper  in  India  than  in  the US,  the  same amount of  rupees was  equivalent  to  an American  income of nearly $2,400.  Similarly,  the average Chinese  income  in 2000 was $840 at the official yuan–dollar market exchange rate, but more than $3,900 if measured on a purchasing power equivalent basis.[4]  

Even if we allow for these differences in the cost of living, the number of people in the  world  who  live  on  the  equivalent  of  $1  per  day,  or  $2  per  day,  is  still depressingly large: according to Sala‐i‐Martin's estimate, nearly 300 million, and not quite  1  billion,  respectively.  But  this  is  far  below  the  1.2  billion  and  2.8  billion figures that have become familiar in public discussion and are used by Stiglitz. More important,  Stiglitz  follows  the  more  familiar  view  in  saying  that  these  totals  are increasing,  but  Sala‐i‐Martin  estimates  that  they  are  declining  despite  the  rapid growth in world population. As a result, he finds, the proportion of people living on what amounts to $1 per day has fallen from 20 percent of the world's population a quarter‐century ago to just 5 percent today, while the $2‐per‐day poverty rate has fallen from 44 percent to 19 percent. 

Much empirical research will have to be done and much analytical debate will have to  take  place  before  anyone  can  confidently  decide  which  of  these  contrasting measurements  is  the  more  accurate.  But  it  is  worth  pointing  out  that  the  major source of  the decline  in poverty over  the  last quarter‐century, according  to Sala‐i‐Martin's calculation, is the dramatic reduction in poverty in China, the world's most populous  country—and  Stiglitz,  too,  praises  China's  performance  as  one  of  the developing  world's  great  recent  economic  success  stories.  (In  keeping  with  his central  theme,  he  argues  that  China  succeeded  in  reforming  its  economy  and reducing its poverty because it  ignored the IMF's advice to  liberalize and privatize abruptly, and instead followed the gradualist approach, adapted to its own situation, which he favors.) To be sure, the plight of many developing countries, especially in sub‐Saharan Africa, remains dire, as Sala‐i‐Martin also points out, and it may well be deteriorating. But if attention is centered on people rather than countries, the great advances made in China, and to a lesser extent in India—which together account for nearly  38  percent  of  the  world's  population—necessarily  represent  a  very significant improvement. 

 

Stiglitz's attack on the IMF raises not just factual (and counterfactual) questions but substantive  issues as well, particularly his argument that  the IMF acts on behalf of banks  and  bondholders,  and  rich  countries more  generally,  and  therefore  against the  interests  of  the  poor.  To  what  extent  is  the  IMF  supposed  to  act  as  lending institutions ordinarily act? Stiglitz complains at length, and with many specific cases to cite, that the IMF violates countries' economic sovereignty when it requires them to  carry out  its policy  recommendations as a  condition  for  its  granting  credit. But don't  responsible  lenders normally  impose  such  conditions on borrowers?  Stiglitz never  acknowledges  that  today  the  IMF  faces  serious  criticism  from  many 

Page 12: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 12 of 14

economists and politicians  in the West on the ground that  it makes  loans with too few  conditions,  so  that  the  borrowing  countries  often  simply  end  up wasting  the money.[5]  

Or should  the  IMF think of  itself not as a  lending  institution, acting as responsible lenders normally do, but instead as an institution charged solely with promoting the welfare  of  the  borrowing  countries,  with  waste  of  some  credits  to  be  expected? Some parts of Stiglitz's complaint are not so much about the IMF per se as about the absence of some form of international authority capable of imposing on citizens who are  already  relatively  well  off  the  burden  of  assisting  their  less  fortunate  fellow human beings elsewhere.  

To  be  sure,  the  world's  rich  countries  could  simply  agree  among  themselves  to devote  a  much  greater  share  of  their  own  incomes  to  foreign  aid  (a  frequently suggested standard is 1 percent of GDP), either out of a sense of moral obligation or in  recognition  that  raising  the  incomes  of  poor  countries  would  create  benefits spilling  over  to  the  industrialized  world  as  well.  But  in  fact  there  is  no  such agreement. The  foreign aid that most rich countries give  is shrinking compared  to their GDP, and the efficacy of such aid is increasingly being challenged anyway.  

Even  within  countries  with  firmly  established  democratic  governments,  there  is always  debate  about  how  generous  such  assistance  should  be  and  what  form  it should take. But a large part of what troubles Stiglitz and many others who share his views of inequality among countries is that there is not only no such agreement but also  no  effective  mechanism—what  he  calls  "systems  of  global  governance"—for even choosing a policy in this important area and then making it stick. The earnest desire  in  some  quarters  for  a  more  formal  approach  to  international  burden‐sharing,  together with  the  equally  sincere  resistance  to  the  idea  among  others,  is nothing new. But it is worth recognizing explicitly that it is central to the question of inequality. 

Moreover, the matter at issue is deeper than simply whether there should or should not be functioning institutions empowered to act, in effect, as a world government. What obligations the citizens of one country owe to citizens of another is a question that goes to the heart of what is involved in being a nation‐state and in acting as a responsible  human  being.  Is  it  morally  legitimate  for  US  citizens  to  pay  taxes  to provide fellow Americans with a minimum standard of health care under Medicaid, or a minimum standard of nutrition through food stamps, that is far above what the average Angolan receives—and not at the same time be willing to pay the costs of bringing  Angola,  and  the  rest  of  the  world's  low‐income  countries,  up  to  that standard? Most  Americans will  readily  answer  yes.  But  as  philosophers  like  John Rawls and Thomas Pogge have argued, wholly apart from the practical benefits that we might gain from alleviating human misery abroad, justifying in moral terms why we owe more to strangers who are close at hand than we owe to strangers who are far away turns out to be complicated and, in the end, extremely difficult. 

Page 13: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 13 of 14

 

Many of the more practical economic elements of Stiglitz's argument are also issues of  long  standing.  He makes  a  strong  case  for  policies  that  favor  gradualism  over "shock  therapy";  that put  the  emphasis  not  on what  developing  countries  have  in common  but  on  how  each  is  different;  that  place  the  concerns  of  the  poor  above those  of  creditors;  that  give  maintaining  full  employment  a  higher  priority  than reducing inflation (at  least when  inflation is  less than 20 percent a year); and that fight poverty and promote economic growth directly,  rather  than merely establish conditions under which economies will be likely to grow, and poverty to decline, on their  own.  There  is  serious  debate  over  each  element  in  this  program.  Stiglitz provides a powerful  logical  case,  together with much by way of both broad‐based evidence and firsthand specifics, to support his side on each of these issues. But his objective is not to give a balanced assessment of the debate. 

Stiglitz has presented, as effectively as it is possible to imagine anyone making it, his side  of  the  argument,  including  the  substantive  case  for  the  kind  of  economic development policies he favors as well as his more specific  indictment of what the IMF  has  done  and why.  His  book  stands  as  a  challenge.  It  is  now  important  that someone  else—if  possible,  someone  who  thinks  and  writes  as  clearly  as  Stiglitz does, and who understands the underlying economic theory as well as he does, and who has a firsthand command of the facts of recent experience comparable to his—take up this challenge by writing the best possible book laying out the other sides of the  argument. What  is  needed  is  not  just  an  attempt  to  answer  Stiglitz's  specific criticisms of the IMF but a book setting out the substantive case both for the specific policies and also for the general policy approach that the IMF has advocated.  

Who  might  write  such  a  book?  The  most  obvious  candidate  is  the  former  MIT economist Stanley Fischer, who throughout the years that Stiglitz's analysis covers was  the  IMF's  first  deputy managing  director—that  is,  the  Fund's  second‐highest ranking official, but for most observers, the person who, far more than anyone else, actually  set  the  direction  of  the  organization's  policies.  Another  is  my  Harvard colleague (now president of the university) Lawrence Summers, who served as the US deputy treasury secretary, and then secretary, during these years. Supporters of the IMF in the academic world, like MIT's Rudiger Dornbusch, may lack the firsthand "who said what to whom" knowledge that comes from high‐level public service, but they  are  clear‐thinking  economists  and  powerful  advocates  nonetheless.  In  the absence of such an answer, however, Stiglitz's book will surely claim a large place on the public stage. It certainly stands as the most forceful argument that has yet been made against the IMF and its policies. 

Notes 

[1] Data from the 1999/2000 World Development Report, Table 2. 

Page 14: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Globalization: Stiglitz's Case By Benjamin M. Friedman Globalization and Its Discontents

Page 14 of 14

[2]  These  are  my  calculations  based  on  data  in  the  2001  World  Development Indicators; 1999 is the latest year for which full data are available. Some countries that are presumably poor enough  to be  in  the "lowest‐income  fifty"—for example, Afghanistan—are  excluded  because  per  capita  income  data  are  not  available  for them. 

[3] "The Disturbing 'Rise' of Global Income Inequality," National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper No. w8904, April 2002. 

[4] Data from the 2002 World Development Report, Table 1. 

[5]  Surprisingly,  Stiglitz  is  not  consistent  in  his  own  treatment  of  the  question  of what  conditions  are  appropriate  for  loans.  He  repeatedly  castigates  the  IMF  for imposing its officials' views over those of government officials  in debtor countries. But he boasts about how the World Bank, where he worked, forced Russia to accept stringent conditions in order to receive a loan. 

 

Letters 

November 21, 2002: Thomas W. Pogge, What Is Poverty? 

 

Page 15: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Review of Joseph E. Stiglitz’s Globalization and its Discontents

(W.W. Norton, New York and London)

Joe Stiglitz has written an important book. It should be read by anyone interested in

economic development, public policy in an era of globalization, and the political economy

of decision making in international organizations. It is part memoir, part manifest, and part

criticism of the International Monetary Fund (IMF). As a memoir, it is entertaining and

informative. It tells the story of how Professor Stiglitz went to Washington, and did not

like it there. He found out that politics was the main sport played inside the beltway, and

that ideology was often more important than rigorous intellectual debate. Worse yet, he got

little respect. People in high places did not always want to listen to him, and when they

did, they often ignored his advice.

As a manifest, the book is powerful. One does not have to agree with everything

Stiglitz has to say, to recognize that many of his ideas are important and deserve to

be discussed seriously. As a result of the debate generated by the book, some policies

that have become readily accepted in Washington are likely to be revised in the

future.

The book is at its weakest when it comes to the criticism of the IMF. And this is not

only because of what Stiglitz has to say; it is mostly because of how he says it. The

tone is overly hostile and aggressive, and he misses no opportunity to insult the IMF

staff. According to Stiglitz, ‘‘intellectual consistency has never been the hall-mark of

the IMF,’’ and the staff systematically practices ‘‘bad economics.’’ His characterizations

of IMF economists and policies are unfair and, in many cases, self-serving. I believe

that the book would have been more effective had Stiglitz chosen a more temperate

style.

1. The main argument

The main tenet of the book is simple, and goes something like this: pro-global-

ization policies have the potential of doing a lot of good, if undertaken properly and if

Book reviews252

Page 16: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

they incorporate the characteristics of each individual country. Countries should

embrace globalization on their own terms, taking into account their own history,

culture, and traditions. However, if poorly designed—or if a cookie-cutter approach is

followed—pro-globalization policies are likely to be costly. They will increase

instability, make countries more vulnerable to external shocks, reduce growth, and

increase poverty.

The problem, according to Stiglitz, is that globalization has not been pushed

carefully, or fairly. On the contrary, liberalization policies have been implemented too

fast, in the wrong order, and often using inadequate—or plainly wrong—economic

analysis. As a consequence, he argues, we now face terrible results, including

increases in destitution and social conflict, and generalized frustration. The culprits

are the IMF and its ‘‘market fundamentalists,’’ the ‘‘Washington Consensus,’’ and the

US Treasury.

Stiglitz believes that in the early 1990s, the IMF, the World Bank and the US

Treasury launched a conspiracy of sorts to run worldwide economic reform—this is the

infamous ‘‘Washington Consensus.’’ This view, however, is overly simplistic and

ignores the evolution of reform thinking during the last two decades. In the 1980s

and early 1990s, policy makers in many developing nations were moving faster than

the multilaterals or the Treasury. In Argentina, Chile, and Mexico, for example, the

reforms were the result of a ‘‘national consensus’’ that was more imaginative, daring

and far-reaching than anything bureaucrats in Washington were willing to accept at that

time. It is well known, for example, that the IMF was initially critical of Chile’s social

security reform, it opposed Argentina’s currency board, and it was highly skeptical of

Mexico’s trade-opening strategy during the mid-1980s. If anything, the original

emphasis on how to undertake economic reform came from a group of developing

countries’ economists—many of them from Latin America—and not from the ranks of

the multilaterals.

Three interrelated policy issues are at the center of Stiglitz’s criticism of global-

ization. (1) In designing reform packages during the 1990s, crucial aspects of the

sequencing and pace of reform were ignored. As a result, in many countries, reform

was implemented too fast—Stiglitz prefers gradualism—and in the wrong order. (2)

Advocating (and imposing) capital account liberalization was a huge mistake. And (3),

the IMF response to crises—and in particular to the East Asian crisis—was a disaster

that made things worse rather than better. In particular, imposing fiscal austerity and

raising interest rates were terrible mistakes that cost the East Asian countries several

points in terms of growth. Not surprisingly, given his theoretical writings during the last

35 years, Stiglitz frames his criticism around the insights of the theory of asymmetric

information.

Stiglitz claims that if things had been done differently, that is, if they had been

done his way, the outcome in terms of social conditions would have been significantly

better. At times, I found his arguments to be persuasive. At other times, however, I

had trouble believing what I was reading, and I had to ask myself if he was being

serious. This was the case, for example, when I read—in pp. 129 and 231—that the

2002 Argentine crisis could have been avoided by following a more expansive fiscal

policy!

Book reviews 253

Page 17: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

2. The sequencing and pace of reform and capital account liberalization

Stiglitz repeatedly argues that for economic liberalization to succeed, it is essential that

reform be implemented at the right speed and in the right sequence (see, for example, pp.

73–78). This is a very important principle, and Stiglitz is right in emphasizing it. I believe

that Stiglitz is particularly on target when he argues that opening the capital account too

soon is likely to generate serious dislocations.

This emphasis on speed and sequencing is not new in policy discussions, however. In

fact, since the beginning of the economics profession, it has been dealt with over and over

again. Adam Smith, for example, argued in The Wealth of Nations that determining the

appropriate sequencing was a difficult issue that involved, primarily, political consider-

ations (see the Cannan Edition, Book IV, Chapter VII, Part III, p. 121). Moreover, Smith

supported gradualism—just as Stiglitz does—on the grounds that cold-turkey liberaliza-

tion would result in a significant increase in unemployment.

In the early 1980s, the World Bank became particularly interested in understanding

issues related to sequencing and speed of reform. Papers were commissioned, conferences

were organized, and different country experiences were explored. As a result of the

discussion surrounding this work, a consensus of sorts developed on the sequencing and

speed of reform. The most important elements of this consensus included: (1) trade

liberalization should be gradual and buttressed with substantial foreign aid; (2) an effort

should be made to minimize the unemployment consequences of reform; (3) in countries

with very high inflation, fiscal imbalances should be dealt with very early on in the reform

process; (4) financial reform requires the creation of modern supervisory and regulatory

agencies; and (5), the capital account should be liberalized at the very end of the process,

and only once the economy has been able to expand successfully its export sector. Of

course, not everyone agreed with all of these recommendations, but most people did. In

particular, people at the IMF did not object to these general principles. For example, Jacob

Frenkel, who was to become the IMF’s Economic Counselor, argued in a mid-1980s

article in the IMF Staff Papers that the capital account should, indeed, be opened towards

the end of the reform process.

Sometime during the early 1990s, this received wisdom on sequencing and speed began

to be challenged. Increasingly, people in Washington began to call for simultaneous and

very fast reforms. Many argued that politically, this was the only way to move forward.

Otherwise, the argument went; reform opponents would successfully block liberalization

efforts. I remember being introduced to this view by an economist turned politician,

Vaclav Klaus. When I met him in Prague in 1991, he said: ‘‘Oh, you are the ‘sequencing’

professor. . .’’ and then he added, ‘‘you got it all wrong. There is not such a thing as an

optimal sequence. We should do as much as we can, as fast as we can.’’ When I asked him

what were the bases of his recommendation, he simply said, ‘‘politics, politics. . .’’ In the

book, Stiglitz is critical of Klaus’s ‘‘rapid and simultaneous’’ reform strategy, but his

criticism fails to address the political economy concerns that at the time worried Klaus and

other pioneer reformers in Central and Eastern Europe.

In 1992, and in response to what was perceived as US pressure to lift controls on

international capital movements, Yung Chul Park from Korea University organized a

conference on capital account liberalization. Most participants agreed that following an

Book reviews254

Page 18: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

appropriate sequencing was vital for the success of liberalization. There was also broad

support for the idea that a premature opening of the capital account could entail serious

danger for the country in question (see S. Edwards (Ed.). Capital Controls, Exchange

Rates and Monetary Policy in the World Economy, Cambridge University Press, 1995). In

a paper presented at this conference, Robert Mundell captured succinctly the views of most

participants. The following quote is illustrative: ‘‘unfortunately. . .there are some negative

externalities [of an early capital account liberalization]. One is that the borrowing goes into

consumption rather than into investment, permitting the capital-importing country to live

beyond its means. . .without any offset in future output with which to service the loans.

Even if the liabilities are entirely in private hands, the government may feel compelled to

transform the unrepayable debt into sovereign debt rather than allow execution of

mortgages or other collateral’’ (p. 20).

At the 1992 Seoul conference on capital liberalization, one of the few dissenters was the

late Manuel Guitian, then a senior official at the IMF, who argued in favor of moving quickly

towards capital account convertibility. Yet, in stark contrast to Stiglitz’s characterization of

the IMF leadership, there was no dogma or arrogance in Guitian’s position. He listened to

others’ arguments, provided counter-arguments, and carefully listened to the counter

counter-arguments. I believe that Guitian’s paper—suggestively titled ‘‘Capital Account

Liberalization: Bringing Policy in Line with Reality’’—is one of the first written pieces that

documents the IMF’s change in views regarding sequencing and capital account convert-

ibility. After discussing the evolution of international financial markets, and expressing

reservations about the ‘‘capital-account-last’’ sequencing recommendation, Guitian sum-

marized his views as follows: ‘‘There does not seem to be an a priori reason why the two

accounts [current and capital] could not be opened up simultaneously. . .[A] strong case canbe made in support of rapid and decisive liberalization in capital transactions’’ (pp. 85–86).

Starting in 1995, more and more countries began to relax their controls on capital

mobility. In doing this, however, they tended to follow different strategies and paths.

While some countries only relaxed bank lending, others only allowed long-term capital

movements, and yet others—such as Chile—used market-based mechanisms to slow down

the rate at which capital was flowing into the economy. Many countries, however, did not

need any prodding from the IMF or the US to open their capital account. Indonesia and

Mexico—just to mention two important cases—had a long tradition of free capital

mobility, which preceded the events discussed in this book, and never had any intention

of following a different policy.

But agreeing that sequencing is important is not the same as saying that capital controls

should never be lifted. A difficult and important policy issue—and one that Stiglitz does

not really tackle in this book—is how and when to remove impediments to capital flows.

Recent research that uses new and improved measures on the degree of capital mobility

suggests that a freer capital account has a positive effect on long run growth in countries

that have surpassed a certain stage in the development process, and have strong institutions

and domestic capital markets. Also, there is some evidence suggesting that price-based and

transparent mechanisms, such as the flexible tax on short-term inflows used by Chile

during much of the 1990s, work relatively well as a transitional device. It allows for some

capital mobility and discourages short-term speculative monies; at the same time, it avoids

arbitrary decisions by bureaucrats. However, as I have argued elsewhere, even Chile-style

Book reviews 255

Page 19: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

capital controls have costs, and they did not spare Chile from contagion or macro

instability during the second half of the 1990s.

3. Crisis management in East Asia

Stiglitz is particularly critical of the way in which the IMF handled the East Asian

crisis. In his view, major mistakes included (1) closing down, in the middle of a financial

panic, a number of banks in Indonesia; (2) bailing out private and mostly foreign creditors;

(3) not allowing the imposition of capital controls on outflows; and (4) imposing tight

fiscal policies and high interest rates. He claims that the experiences of China and India,

two countries that did not suffer a crisis, and of Malaysia—which did not follow the IMF’s

advice, and recovered quickly—support his views. This argument is highly unpersuasive,

however. Anyone mildly informed knows that there are many reasons why India and

China have not faced a crisis, and attributing this to the presence of capital controls is

overly simplistic, if not plainly wrong. The case of Malaysia is a bit more complicated. It

has recovered fast—although not as fast as South Korea—but it is not clear if this recovery

has been the result of the imposition of capital controls. What is clear, however, is that

Malaysia surprised many observers by tightening controls only temporarily; after approx-

imately a year, and once the economy had stabilized, the controls were lifted just as Dr.

Mahatir had originally announced.

What makes Malaysia’s case particularly interesting is that historically the temporary

use of controls is quite unique. The historical norm is closer to what happened in Latin

America during the 1980s debt crisis, when what was supposed to be a temporary

tightening of controls, became a long-term feature of the regional economies. Moreover, in

Latin America, the stricter controls on capital outflows did not encourage the restructuring

of the domestic economies, nor did they result in orderly reforms. The opposite, in fact,

happened. In country after country politicians experimented with populist policies that at

the end of the road deepened the crisis.

Two of Stiglitz’s criticisms are right on target: closing banks in the midst of a panic is a

major mistake. Also, massive bailouts are costly and ineffective. A number of people have

long recognized this, and the recent proposal by Anne Krueger, the IMF’s First Deputy

Managing Director, is a positive development in an effort to implement an effective

standstills framework.

Stiglitz’ most severe criticism refers to the IMF’s fiscal and interest rate policies. He

argues that the East Asian crisis called for expansionary and not, as the IMF insisted,

contractionary fiscal policies. In his view, by imposing fiscal retrenchment, the IMF made

a serious recession even deeper. Worse yet, the IMF-mandated increases in interest rates

generated a string of bankruptcies that deepened the confidence crisis and further

contributed to the slowdown. Stiglitz’s position, however, does not have—at least, not

yet—much empirical support, and fails to recognize how severe the situation had become

by late 1997. These were not, as he argues, ‘‘severe downturns’’ that required textbook-

type counter-cyclical fiscal policies; these were major currency crises. And a key feature

of currency crises is that the public drastically reduces its demand for government

securities and domestic money, turning to safer assets, especially foreign exchange. This

Book reviews256

Page 20: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

constrains what governments in crisis countries can do: with a declining demand for

government securities—by both local and foreign investors—it is very difficult to run a

more expansionary fiscal policy unless the deficit is monetized. Moreover, if the decline in

the demand for domestic money is not brought to an end, the price of foreign exchange

will jump drastically—greatly overshooting its equilibrium level—and inflation will

increase significantly. If foreign currency denominated debt is high—as was the case in

a number of the East Asian countries—the weakening of the currency will result in a

significantly higher debt burden and further bankruptcies.

The first order of business in a major currency crisis is to re-establish confidence. While

massive and recurrent bankruptcies do not contribute towards achieving this goal, neither

do large deficits translated into money printing, or rapidly depreciating exchange rates. At

the end of the road, the issue is one of trade-offs, and the key question is by how much to

let the exchange rate depreciate, and by how much—and for how long—to increase

interest rates. The answer depends in part on the government’s objectives. If the authorities

want to avoid default and runaway inflation—clear key objectives of every East Asian

government—letting the exchange rate run amok is highly risky. Under most circum-

stances, pumping in liquidity when the demand for money is shrinking, and issuing

government debt when government securities are being dumped, is unlikely to restore

confidence or avoid an inflationary explosion.

4. Concluding remarks

I finish where I began: This is an important book that deserves to be read and discussed

widely. At the end of the road, however, I was left with a sense of emptiness. I have no doubt

that Stiglitz is sincere, and that he is truly pained by what he believes are major problems

with globalization. However, he is also rather naı̈ve. And it is this naivete, and not the

stridency of the delivery, what at the end makes this book fail. Stiglitz has too much

confidence on the ability of governments to do the right thing, and he exaggerates greatly the

extent of market failures. The agenda should be to improve institutions and incentives; to

promote competition and efficiency; to implement policies that raise productivity; to truly

help the poor and the destitute; to put an end to corruption and abuse; and to make sure that

globalization becomes a fair process, where the industrial countries also dismantle their

protective barriers. The agenda should not be to bring back bureaucrats, xenophobic auto-

crats, and corrupt politicians to run the economy. We have been there, and it does not work.

Sebastian Edwards

University of California,

Los Angeles, CA, USA

National Bureau of Economic Research, Cambridge, USA

E-mail address: [email protected]

9 September 2002

PII: S0304 -3878 (02 )00097 -4

Book reviews 257

Page 21: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Journal of Libertarian StudiesVolume 18, no. 1 (Winter 2004), pp. 89–98

2004 Ludwig von Mises Institutewww.mises.org

89

BOOK REVIEWSEdited by N. Stephan Kinsella*

JOSEPH E. STIGLITZ. GLOBALIZATION AND ITS DISCONTENTS.NEW YORK: W.W. NORTON, 2002. PP. xxii + 282.

Globalization and its Discontents is an enjoyable and thought-provoking book. It is probably the most readable, well-argued, andsubtle attack against globalization in the past few years. Although theauthor fights, in a rather dogmatic style with some shades of arrogance,against what he believes to be devious free-market attitudes, his proseis simple and accessible to a wide audience. But it is also deceptive.While the author emphasizes time and again that he is not levelingan attack against market principles and globalization in general, headvocates Keynesian policymaking (money printing and deficit spend-ing) on virtually every page.

It is an enjoyable book for the reader in search of the perfect world,and it suits the well-meaning anti-globalist who believes that sinceindividuals make mistakes, it is wiser to give other individuals theright to interfere. Put differently, Stiglitz strongly believes that badpolicymaking can be reduced by enlightened policymaking, both na-tionally and on a global scale. And that when international economicagencies do not behave properly, they must be reformed, made moretransparent and accountable, and less dependent on special interests.

The author believes that national leaders, by and large, pursue thewell-being of their peoples. He also believes that international agencies,like the IMF and the World Bank, must ensure that global phenomenamaintain a “human face,” and that national politicians be supported bysomebody in charge when something goes wrong. Indeed, it is hardto see much economics in these conclusions (see in particular the final

*General Counsel, Applied Optoelectronics, Inc. To submit reviews for thissection, visit www.stephankinsella.com/jls.

Page 22: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Journal of Libertarian Studies 18, no. 1 (Winter 2004)

90

chapter of the book). Some readers might also question its logic. Asthe following pages will explain, these doubts are justified.

The foreword to the book sets the pace. While taking good care toinform the possibly unaware reader about his fundamental contribu-tions to economic science, Professor Stiglitz, the 2001 Nobel Laureate,reveals that he became interested in real-world matters in 1993 whenhe joined the Clinton administration. He later continued his career atthe World Bank where he was chief economist and senior vice presi-dent. The author claims that this book is the result of those eye-openingexperiences, during which he found out that decision-making processesare often influenced by politics and ideology. He further realized thatglobalization without governance often leads to devastating results,especially on Less Developed Countries (LDCs).

Surprisingly, however, the core argument of the book is not theanalysis of the causal link between ideology, politics, and economicperformance in a globalized world. Rather, the author keeps concen-trating on bad policymaking carried out both by Western nationalgovernments and by international organizations. He posits a directcausal link between globalization and bad policymaking, and con-cludes by suggesting suitable rules for global economic management.According to Stiglitz, these rules should be fairness and consensus,and they should be designed through a democratic process so as toguarantee social justice and meet the needs of everybody.

His thesis is not developed in a theoretically consistent framework.Instead, the author offers a list of case studies in bad economics andpolicymaking by the IMF and the U.S. Treasury. The next paragraphswill therefore reconsider the main issues raised by Stiglitz, highlighthis most important arguments, and underscore some factual and meth-odological puzzles, these being in fact equivalent to a number ofimplicit assumptions.

POLITICALLY CORRECT MISCONCEPTIONSABOUT FREE MARKET ECONOMICS

Although much of the text (for instance, the first chapter) focuseson poverty and globalization, Stiglitz does not state explicitly that pov-erty is the consequence of globalization. On the contrary, in chapternine, he states clearly that the origin of all problems is the way global-ization has been managed, rather than globalization per se. In particu-lar, he feels that since mainstream economists became the managersof the globalization process, people have been betrayed, especially in

Page 23: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Book Reviews

91

LDCs. He adds that globalization policies and institutions—includingthe IMF and U.S. government—provoked a number of shocks that ledentire countries to major crises and disasters. Thus, Western global-izers should take the blame for such failures, since they made emptypromises and forced many LDCs to undertake suicidal steps towardliberalization.

As a matter of fact, Stiglitz never really defines what he meansby the term “globalization.” From a free-market perspective, glob-alization refers to the freedom to choose among opportunities avail-able on a global scale: Buyers are free to maximize their purchasingpower, and sellers are free to compete in order to satisfy consumers’needs and remunerate the scarce resources they use. In other words,globalization stands for a world of opportunities opened to buyers andthe end of privileges for sellers. It is, therefore, manifest that global-ization is an improvement for those who are allowed to choose, andfor those who can successfully satisfy buyers’ needs. But it is irrele-vant for those who cannot choose—where more-or-less altruistic poli-cymakers decide on their behalf—and it is even harmful for those whoenjoy normative privileges.

However, none of the above characterizes Stiglitz’s thought. Onecan guess that from his standpoint, globalization is little more than apromise generated by free-market fundamentalists—this being a syn-onym for neoclassical scholars, experts, and selected bureaucrats. Con-sistent with this view, whenever a country failed to grow after its rul-ers were exposed to neoclassical advisors, globalization is assumedto have been aborted. Once this rather bizarre definition of globaliza-tion is accepted, his book can be perceived as an instructive guide tothe misdeeds of neoclassical scholarship and the alibis it has providedto widespread criminal behavior. His account of the Russian crisis(chapter five) is a good example.

However, the argument runs into trouble when the author suggeststhat the solution to neoclassical policymaking is some kind of paternal-istic Third Way managed by caring and altruistic politicians devotedto achieving full employment. In particular, he ignores the possibilityof having made a mistake by equating globalization with neoclassicalthinking. And he seems to be totally unaware of the fact that the al-ternative to mainstream economics is not enlightened and expandedgovernance structures, but rather, to echo Mises’s wording, freedomto choose and discard. These oversights characterize both the author’sinterpretations of the crises and his view about what could have beendone instead.

Page 24: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Journal of Libertarian Studies 18, no. 1 (Winter 2004)

92

These decisive misunderstandings are apparent from the veryfirst pages. While acknowledging that free capital movements andfree trade have enhanced living standards in vast areas of the world,Stiglitz remarks that during the age of globalization, the poverty gaphas not been reduced. He forgets to tell the reader that most LDCs,where living standards are stagnating and people keep dying becauseof poverty and civil wars, have hardly been touched by globalizationor, more generally, by economic freedom. Accusing globalizationfor aborted economic growth in Africa since the end of colonialismis not only trite and inaccurate, it is ridiculous.

As for destabilization, Stiglitz seems to be the victim of his ownunderstanding of the free-market process. One does not need a doctor-ate to know that free-market economics is about preventing policy-makers from interfering in peaceful activities voluntarily undertakenby individuals. And it does not take much to see that if market forcesare set free, but policymakers do not withdraw and privileges do notdisappear, the system sooner or later breaks down. Still, the bookignores these basics, and actually eliminates the whole question byassuming with apparent casualness that there are many different formsof free markets (chapter nine).

Finally, the book falls in line with the well-known mantra wherebyall the evils of the developing world are the consequence of presentor past Western behavior. For instance, in Stiglitz’s view, Westernglobalizers forced LDCs to reduce their trade barriers and de factocreated huge trade deficits while destroying fragile production struc-tures. That is not just a terminological question or a somersault inlogic; it is bad economics. One wonders what happened to exchangerates. Free trade (and globalization) is a game whereby you cannothave losers, such as import-competing industries, without also havingwinners, such as exporters. Put differently, you can’t have importsunless you have exports to pay for them. Maybe exchange rates didnot depreciate enough because they were fixed and the local currencywas not convertible, or perhaps because foreign aid made sure thatcheap imports could flow in.

Whatever the correct answer is, globalization has nothing to dowith fixed exchange rates and inconvertible currencies. And if the Westis guilty of providing too much aid to the leaders of poor countries, asis probably true, Stiglitz should say so. But he doesn’t. Indeed, whenhe mentions the evils of fixed exchange rates, the author attributes themto the inconsistencies of the globalizers. Surely, Western protectionism

Page 25: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Book Reviews

93

hasn’t made life easy for third world countries, but protectionism isthe opposite of globalization. It is wrong to claim that the best pol-icy against protectionism is central planning with a human face orenlightened governance.

CASE STUDIES

After having suggested that globalization is the result of badpolicymaking enforced by the IMF and, to a lesser extent, by theWorld Bank and the WTO (chapter one), the rest of the book is, byand large, a sequence of anecdotes and case studies. On one side,Stiglitz describes the blind bureaucrats from the IMF, the repentedbut weak employees of the World Bank, and the greedy Americanestablishment that fought communism but forgot about democracy.On the other side, we meet the author himself, who modestly explainshow he abandoned the academic world in order to solve America’seconomic problems and, having done that, decided to move on tosolve world poverty. As the reader soon finds out, the author faceddisappointment, but fought hard and almost single-handedly to stopIMF colonialism.

Stiglitz’s cases are persuasive, but somewhat irrelevant and decep-tive. They are beside the point, since it is a gross mistake to considerneoclassical constructivism as a synonym for globalization. They aredeceptive, for although it is undeniable that advocating capital-marketsliberalization in, say, Ethiopia, may harm domestic banks if they areunable to offer good enough credit conditions to borrowers, it is wrongto conclude that farmers suffer as a result. Unfortunately, this rhe-torical strategy is a recurrent feature of the book.

Stiglitz offers various counterexamples to the development strate-gies recommended by the IMF. In particular, his implicit thesis isthat countries that turned down IMF advice did well. One case isBotswana (chapter two) which, incidentally, ranks relatively high (andhigher than Ethiopia) in the Index of Economic Freedom. Anothercase is China (chapter three). It would be hard to deny that Botswanawas right in rejecting IMF policymaking and constraints, or that thepolitical power of China was no match for any IMF bureaucrat. Butthe Botswana case does not demonstrate that the country’s successeswere due to socialist planning, enhanced regulation, protectionism, orexpansion in the bureaucracy. Nor would one claim that the Chineseleaders succeeded because they introduced further regulation and cen-tralized planning in the past two decades.

Page 26: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Journal of Libertarian Studies 18, no. 1 (Winter 2004)

94

Indeed, Stiglitz does not do it, either. As mentioned earlier, henever says that globalization per se is bad. He simply states that open-ing up may be beneficial if some preliminary conditions are met, andthat good governments can do desirable things. He hastily concludesthat whenever free-market blueprints failed, the explanations lie withWestern economic and political interference, starting with the IMFand U.S. Government, which forced good politicians to open up tooquickly. As a result, civil servants became corrupt, jobs were destroyed,and easy imports, foreign bankers, and high interest rates choked de-velopment. Finally, social tensions erupted, in some cases leading tocivil wars.

POLICIES

The economics of IMF policymaking occupies most of the book,since the author frequently deals with privatization, liberalization, for-eign direct investment, social tensions, and poverty. A review is notthe right place to discuss in detail the fragility of neoclassical econom-ics in these areas, which is the main goal of the author throughoutthe book. It may be enough to underscore Stiglitz’s main ponts. First,he argues, although too much government intervention is bad, thereare plenty of good things a government can do if properly enlightenedand informed, presumably by reformed international agencies. Second,the market does not yield perfect results, so free-market economicsis wrong unless proper institutions are in place, fairness enforced, andfull employment guaranteed. Third, the IMF was originally createdto get things right by following Keynesian guidelines, but was soonseduced by the dream of the invisible hand. Rather than accomplish-ing its original and true mission, it ended up colluding with Westernfinancial capitalism and pressure groups.

Once again, the reader is offered various examples:

• free trade, where imports are paid through foreign aid andexchange rates are irrelevant;

• free capital markets, which would undermine much-neededsubsidies and expose debtors to the consequences of bad rep-utations or bad borrowing decisions; and

• price liberalization, which would be unfair to inefficient orbadly located producers.

The argument is further developed in chapters four to seven, inwhich the Southeast Asian and the Russian crises are explored in detail,

Page 27: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Book Reviews

95

and where the virtues of gradual Keynesian transitions are opposedto the evils of IMF-style shock therapies. At this stage, Stiglitz’s ap-proach should no longer surprise the reader. Let us consider the Asiancase. In his view, Southeast Asia’s economies were doing fine until theWest forced them to open up their capital markets, destroy the miracle,and cause what the author defines as the most dramatic economiccrisis since the Great Depression.

However, some caution is in order. Although Stiglitz singles outIndonesia, Korea, and Thailand to illustrate the catastrophe, the well-informed reader cannot help remembering that in 2002, five yearsafter the 1997 crisis blew up, real GDP in those three countries wasrespectively 99%, 124%, and 105% of its pre-crisis level. As for thealleged domino effect, real GDP in developing Asia in 2002 was 33%higher than just before the crisis.1

Never mind the figures. Stiglitz is quite right in saying that the IMFshould have kept out of the whole story, but he is wrong in saying thatthose countries were in good shape prior to IMF intervention, and thatthe IMF precipitated the crisis. Indeed, why would speculators attackthese countries if they were in such healthy conditions to begin with?The truth of the matter is that globalization exposed economic dis-tortions and malfunctions, but the IMF delayed the moment whenthe distortions were exposed. The redistributive patchwork advo-cated by Stiglitz may appear to help temporarily, but they are merewindow dressing, and can hardly fix a sick system, as the Asian crisisdemonstrates. It is deplorable that the IMF played the window-dressinggame first, and then provided funds to bail out selected lenders.

Instead, the author accuses the IMF of having served Westernfinancial interests and having disregarded fairness, although the readerwill look in vain for a clear definition of fairness. He will find just ahint in chapters three and seven, where Stiglitz refers to fairness asone of the key elements of the social contract—the other being fullemployment. The author does not bother to explain by whom andwhere this contract was signed, nor does he clarify what was written init. Nonetheless, it is clear to him that governments broke the contractby not pursuing fairness, so violent attitudes by the residents were al-most legitimized. Put differently, he is persuaded that income transfersare one of the fundamental human rights, rather than being an abuse

1International Monetary Fund, World Economic Outlook (Sept. 2003), sta-tistical appendix: “Output.”

Page 28: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Journal of Libertarian Studies 18, no. 1 (Winter 2004)

96

by some at the expense of others. The IMF and the Washington con-sensus are therefore guilty, since they forced national governments torenege upon the social contracts.

GENERAL ISSUES

As a matter of fact, if the reader forgets about the author’s flightsinto morality, the main problem with the book appears to be its title,which should have been related to the economics and politics of inter-national agencies (the IMF in particular) and of the U.S. government,rather than to globalization. Once again, Stiglitz says very little aboutglobalization, and what he says rests on questionable foundations.Globalization is about deregulation and low taxation. These are notquite the same thing as active central banking, fixed exchange rates,and high taxation, which are the core components of many IMF poli-cies and macro-rescue plans in the past three decades.

As has been argued above, the author neglects the distinction, anddevelops three main theses. First, international agencies have done apoor job by trying to enforce neoclassical recipes. They have aggra-vated the economic conditions in many LDCs, and raised bad feelingsagainst anything coming from the West, and from the U.S. in particu-lar. Second, despite their past misdeeds, international agencies per seare not a bad idea. Their primary goal should, however, be restrictedto the provision of sound information and unconditional aid. Third,opening up (globalization) should not be rejected in principle, butdecisions about its timing, depth, and features should be a matter foreach national government to decide, especially when politicians are ofgood quality, and they demonstrate an ability to preserve consensus.

From a policymaking viewpoint, Stiglitz does not consistently ad-vocate a worldwide governance scheme for globalization. Global gov-ernance by enlightened and compassionate international bodies isdesirable, in his opinion, but each government should also be free toact as it judges appropriate. As for the meaning of the expression “goodgovernment,” he recommends fairness as the primary criterion to betaken into account for any development policy (chapter three). Nev-ertheless, one is left wondering about who decides what is fair, andwhether Stiglitz would be willing to accept the notion of fairness thatmany national governments have enforced in the past decades, irre-spective of IMF intervention.

Consistent with his assumption about fairness, Stiglitz considersprivatization and liberalization attractive, but only if they guarantee

Page 29: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Book Reviews

97

extra jobs at fair conditions. Hence, his thesis in favour of conditionalglobalization and of policies aimed at spreading the costs if anythingundesirable happens—including bad lending and investment. There-fore, bad entrepreneurs should not be allowed to fail, but should berescued through money printing. After all, he argues, a little inflationis preferable to widespread poverty and civil war. It is not a new the-sis, and we leave it to the reader to evaluate the extent to which moneyprinting can solve the problems of faulty management and bad govern-ment, and whether it can provide suitable incentives for entrepreneu-rial activities or fairness to those layers of the population who cannotprotect themselves against inflation.

ONE CONCLUDING REMARK

This book illustrates and contributes significantly to one grossmisconception about globalization: Globalization does not identifypolicies, neither from neoclassical nor from Keynesian quarters. Wedo not know how people want to behave, what kind of safeguards theyprefer to have, or how much they are willing to pay for them. Free-market globalizers have nothing to say about that, and believe thatnobody has. This justifies Professor Stiglitz when he correctly criticizesIMF policymaking and inconsistencies (chapter eight), and it alsoexplains why he is in trouble when he suggests recipes that go beyondgeneric, but nevertheless treacherous, notions such as fairness andsocial consensus, almost bordering on demagoguery. See for instancechapter eight, where he confronts the legitimacy of property rightswith that of the social contract.

Instead, globalization is about the freedom to opt out of the pro-posed policies. As the Russian case demonstrates, a market systemrests on widely accepted behavioral rules. Stiglitz deserves credit forpointing out that Western consultants have contributed to suffocatingor destroying those rules. He also deserves credit for hinting thatthose consultants also helped centralized policy-making retain itscoercive power so that rent-seeking and collusion with the policy-maker continued to be the winning strategy (chapter seven). Of course,it is hardly surprising that under such conditions, alternative systemshave not come to the surface, but it is puzzling to see that the authorbelieves this to be the essence or the consequence of globalization.On the contrary, globalization in Russia and in some other countriesof the Soviet Empire was never the name of the game. Put differently,Stiglitz succeeds in showing the game and excels in describing it (see

Page 30: Stiglitz. Globalization and Its Discontents 1

Journal of Libertarian Studies 18, no. 1 (Winter 2004)

98

chapters six and seven), but equally frequently fails to call it by itsproper name: neoclassical constructivism.

ENRICO COLOMBATTO

University of [email protected]