freeden_thepoliticalinpoliticaltheory_05

Upload: hernan-cuevas-valenzuela

Post on 03-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    1/22

    What Should the Political in Political

    Theory Explore?*

    Michael FreedenPolitics, Mansfield College, Oxford

    I. THE GAP IN POLITICAL THEORY

    IT is now commonplace among ever-increasing numbers of political theorists

    to query the state of the art of the sub-discipline, in particular the

    epistemological and ideal-type disposition of contemporary political philosophy.

    But it is less common to detail research agenda that attempt to redress the

    balance and reconnect political theory to the domain of politics. Prior to

    accomplishing that, a lacuna has to be identifieda gap that exists prominently

    between the main schools that currently occupy centre stage in the study of

    political thought.

    Political philosophy, the history of political thought and, more recently, what

    could be very loosely called post-structural or continental1 political theoryhave virtually monopolized the analysis of political thinking; yet, as I shall claim,

    they do not cover the field of what constitutes political thought. Political

    philosophy brings to the study of political theory an overriding concern with

    either or both of the following: the logical validity and argumentative coherence

    of the political philosophy in question, or the moral rightness of the prescriptions

    it contains. Many of its versions display a flight from the political, the crowding

    out of diversity and the shrinking of the political to an area of constructed

    consensus guided by a vision of the good life; while its methods rely heavily onthought experiments and frequently inapplicable modelling. The history of

    political thought brings to the study of political theory an overriding concern

    with the genealogy of arguments, with the conditions for their stability and the

    causes for their transformation, with contexts, reconstructions of intentions, and

    changing horizons of interpretation but, with a few notable exceptions, sacrifices

    synchrony for diachrony. Much post-structuralist thought regards politics as

    obfuscating reality through the articulation of illusions and false categories,

    while expressing deep distrust towards politics as it is, and is overridingly

    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 13, Number 2, 2005, pp. 113134

    Blackwell Publishing, 2005, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 238 Main Street,Cambridge, MA 02142, USA.

    *This article is part of an ESRC-funded research programme on the political theory of politicson which I am engaged.

    1Continental refers less to a geographical entity than to a school, much as the label Anglo-American does.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    2/22

    concerned with reformulating the political through alternative radical ethical

    discourses that emphasize transparency, the recognition of identity, equality

    and diversity, and empowering. All three schools perform crucial roles in our

    understanding of political theories and in the uses to which we can put them.

    But their very success papers over an undeniable lack: how do we study political

    thought from within the discipline of politics? On what kind of political theory

    ought we to focus, as students of politics and political phenomena, bearing in

    mind some central characteristics of political concepts and language? In this

    article I offer some exploratory thoughts on the subject.

    Much has been written about the shortcomings of current political theory on

    the metapractical and metatheoretical levels. Thus, John Gunnells seminal books

    have exposed glaring weaknesses in the methods and issues pursued by Western

    political theorists.2 Other instances are offered by theorists such as BenjaminBarber and Bonnie Honig.3 Nor do I wish to belittle the extraordinary work

    done by philosophers and historiansI count myself as a member of both camps.

    But the fact is that most political theory employs methodological paradigms

    imported from disciplines external to politics: philosophy and history. They are

    consequently bound to treat political theory as a sub-set of a larger enterprise,

    philosophical or historical, however illuminating those perspectives are to the

    appreciation of political thought, and however crystallized the respective sub-

    enterprises have been in the grand traditions and discourses of political thought.

    II. THE POLITICAL THEORY OF POLITICS

    This article puts the case for a fourth approach to the study of political theory:

    the political theory of politics. It is not intended to replace its illustrious and

    central predecessors, but to offer another dimension: to supply the kind of

    political theory designed to make immediate, rather than indirect, sense of

    political thought phenomena, and to equip political theorists with tools they

    might wish to employ as students of politics simpliciterthrough the political

    features embedded in thinking about politics. And it is not, as many alternative

    attempts to reconnect theory and practice have been, primarily another form of

    normative political theory. Instead, while recognizing the fundamental ethical

    concerns of political theorists, it points out that the scholarly study of politics

    as is common among political scientistsengages notably in understanding and

    in interpretative mapping. That task should not be abandoned by political

    theorists who are, after all, crucially focused on the meaning of political thinking;

    indeed, exploring that meaning should therefore also be located empirically in

    114 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    2Recently, John G. Gunnell, The Orders of Discourse (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield,1998).

    3B. Barber, The Conquest of Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988); B. Honig,Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993). Bothemphasise the malady rather than the cure, or see the cure in terms of new ethical dimensions.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    3/22

    concrete societies. The consequent analysis will fashion a significant branch of

    political theory dedicated to identifying the political and making sense of it.

    In turn, that appreciation will offer a vital tooland welcome limiting

    frameworkfor ethicists and philosophers engaged in constructing their

    exercises in normative improvement.

    The challenge for political theorists, then, is to distinguish an area they wish

    to term the political and then to develop strategies that enable them to address

    directly issues ofpoliticalthought. In part, this may require the inclusion of new

    source-material that qualifies as thinking about politics.4 But for the most part,

    it involves asking a new set of questions of existing texts, utterances, discourses,

    and practices, reassessing the relative importance of their diverse messages, and

    preparing different methodologies through which to interpret them. That is,

    incidentally, what I understand by the study of ideology in its broadest sense. Itis not a specialized study of certain doctrines, but a particular approach to the

    study of political thinking as such. It views access to our understanding of

    political thinking as always mediated through its spatially and temporally

    contextualized instances; it regards political thinking as a ubiquitous and normal

    aspect of social life; and it insists that political theory must also (though not

    only) encompass these phenomena.

    Politics consists centrally of the area of collective social life that involves

    decision-making, the ranking of policy options, the regulation of dissent, themobilization of support for those activities, and the construction of political

    visions. That is not intended as a definition, nor am I unaware of competing and

    different perspectives on politics relating to the legal standing of states, or to the

    good life or, conversely, to a state of dehumanizing subjugation. But we need to

    make a start, and that is one kind of beginning. It enlists three postulates: First,

    thinkingabout politics significantly relates to the above political issues. Second,

    thinking about politics relates importantly to the political thinking actually

    taking place within political entities: the thinking produced by human beings in

    their political capacity as decision-makers, option-rankers, dissent and conflict

    regulators, support mobilizers, and vision creators; and the thinking consumed

    by them in that capacity. Politics may have been termed the art of the possible,

    but it is a possible based on the feasible and its study has always focused on

    the here and now,5 whether in complacent or critical mode. Third, inasmuch as

    politics is a social and not merely an individual activity, so too is political

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 115

    4This point is persuasively made by Pierre Rosanvallon, Towards a Philosophical History of the

    Political, The History of Political Thought in National Context, ed. D. Castiglione and I. Hampsher-Monk (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 189203, although he also relates thisto the French focus on mentalits. The study of concrete political thought and the study ofmentalitsis similar, but the differences lie mainly in the equal emphasis the latter assigns to a broad range ofpolitical culture, while the former foregrounds political thought and concepts against a backdrop ofpolitical culture.

    5By which I mean not on the immediate present but on current and recent politics, withramifications to more distant paths and beckoning futures. Comparative politics extends the hereto various parts of the globe but follows roughly the same temporal pattern.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    4/22

    thinking. Therefore the latter, too, has to be examined as a series of interactions,

    of collective conduct, of loosely patterned human thought-practices.6

    Of course, the notions of decision, conflict and supportand even the

    production of political visions, as attempts to control the future or to give vent

    to political emotionrevolve around the concept of power. There is no escaping

    that politics is about power and there is consequently no escaping that good

    political theory needs to give plausible accounts of what is entailed, in the

    broadest sense, by political thinking relevant to power. All this is hardly made

    easier by the fact that so many political theorists, as distinct from institutional

    and behavioural analysts, shy away from exploring and understanding power.7

    As a tradition, Anglo-American analytical political philosophy, informed by

    liberalism, is deeply embarrassed by power and tends to ignore it. As a tradition,

    continental political thought and discourse, to the contrary, sees power aspervading and distorting the networks of human interaction, but offers no clear

    ways of eliminating that unfortunate by-product of oppressive and invasive

    human relationships. Both cannot deal with power as a normal, indeed pivotal,

    political phenomenon and as a potential resource to be harnessed to the

    attainment of human and social ends. While Anglo-American political

    philosophy is manic about the feasibility of socio-political relationships without

    power, the continental tradition is depressive about their saturation with power.

    If that seems to return us to what may initially appear to be conventionalissues that characterize politics, there is nothing intrinsically wrong with that.

    Psychology still revolves around human personality and economics around

    scarcity, no matter which complex intellectual constructs shape their elaboration.

    Far more significant is, first, that the approach we need to foster towards those

    issues be innovative, not one employed by most existing schools and, second,

    that we also include more esoteric terms and problems, esoteric only in the

    sense that they are not saliently on the agenda of philosophical students of

    justice, or on the curriculum of undergraduate courses on political theory.

    Political thinking requires analysis as a fluid set of conceptual and discursive

    encounters with issues such as the following: manufacturing stability, handling

    coercion, the conceptual control of political space and political time, the

    management of diversity, ambiguity as controlled indeterminacy, ranking

    and prioritizing (or rationing) demands and values, political

    commitment/allegiancein addition to political obligationas mobilizing

    concepts, and the conceptualization and rhetorical marketing of political failure.

    All those are some of the most typical and central issues on which societies focus

    when they think consciouslyat any level of articulation and sophistication

    116 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    6By a thought-practice I mean an identifiable, patterned and recurrent sequence of thinking, nota physical activity that can be observed directly in the world.

    7The introduction of the notion of empowering, mainly in late 20th century feminist discourse,attempts to relate power to theories of autonomy and self-development, and functions primarily asa code for the latter concepts.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    5/22

    about politics and which, further, are reflected unconsciously in their practices.

    They are the everyday flesh and blood of political debate and discourse and

    through them we can put our finger on the pulse of the body politic.

    In short, we need to find new ways through which to make political thought,

    and its study, work for us. In so doing we must rely heavily on the wisdom and

    understandings derived from the fields of political philosophy and the history of

    political thought. But we may also realize why some of the methods designed to

    satisfy the intellectual concerns of those two disciplines will produce wrong

    results for the purposes set out above.

    III. DECISIONS IN THE LIGHT OF AMBIGUITY, INDETERMINACY,

    INCONCLUSIVENESS AND VAGUENESS

    I can only briefly illustrate some topics and ways of discussing them as part of

    a larger research project I am undertaking. Let me begin with political decision-

    making. A decision involves a choice among options, and a political decision

    involves making such choices for, and/or shaped by, a collectivity. Implicit in the

    concept of choice is the notion of pluralism, at the very least in the sense that

    more than one option is possible (arguably necessary) when a decision is made.

    To that are added two further assumptions, namely, that it is normal and

    unavoidable in any society for more than one voice to exist (even if other voicesare suppressed, they are never quite eliminated); and that making choices is

    necessarily an exercise in ranking. Political theory offers us one highly useful

    instrument for understanding the nature of decision-making: the notion of

    essential contestability. In its advanced formulations, it suggests, first, that

    political concepts are composed of multiple components, not all of which can

    be contained in any given formulation of the concept; and, second, that the

    relative weight of each component is itself variable and the ranking of values

    is hence inconclusive.8 Consequently there can be no unequivocal way of

    choosing among the various conceptions of a concept and arriving at a conclusive

    definition, of which more below.

    In order to appreciate the linguistic and semantic features that guide the

    operation of political concepts, and that have immediate bearing on the

    structuring of political debate, theory, and action, we need to unpack further

    some of the attributes of those concepts, with particular regard to the manner

    through which they impart, or fail to impart, meaning. In political science

    literature, policies are often depicted as being ambiguous.9 Ambiguity relates to

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 117

    8See M. Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach (Oxford: ClarendonPress, 1996), pp. 5560. For my most recent thoughts on the subject see M. Freeden, Essentialcontestability and effective contestability,Journal of Political Ideologies, 9 (2004), 311, 225.

    9See, e.g., James G. Marsh and Johan P. Olsen, Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations (Bergen:Universitetsvorlaget, 1976); William E. Connolly, Politics and Ambiguity (Madison, WI: Universityof Wisconsin Press, 1987).

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    6/22

    more than one reading of a practice, image or text by its consumer. As Empson

    suggested in his classic work, ambiguity is any verbal nuance, however slight,

    which gives room for alternative reactions to the same piece of language.10 But

    implicit in ambiguity is the possibility of there being clear choices among fixed

    and finite meanings, meanings obfuscated through semantic duality (bank) or

    through structural and lexical fluidity (I saw the man with my binoculars), or

    through insufficient information-cum-context (Wittgensteins duck-hare). The

    multiple interpretations of an ambiguous message are potentially dealt with

    through disambiguation: a rephrasing aimed at removing all meanings but one.

    Crucially for politics, ambiguity may be intentional as well as unintentional.

    Ambiguity is often confused with indeterminacy. But indeterminacy is a

    different attribute of political concepts. First, it is a function of their far greater

    complexity. We can create a world in which ambiguities are removed, but thatwould be one based on exceedingly simple premises. The prime minister is the

    leader of the Labour party is a statement where the office, its holder and the

    official status of leadership are subject to clear and generally accepted semantic

    rules and, contextually, party does not denote some kind of festive celebration.

    This state is democratic allows for no such disambiguation, because

    democracy is not ambiguous; it is indeterminate. Indeed, it would be impossible

    to construct a sentence in which all the components of democracy would be

    sufficiently disambiguated for an uncontroversial meaning to emerge. Second,indeterminacy refers to an inevitable and ineliminable contingency of meaning.

    It is a prior ontological standpoint about the impossibility of arriving at fixed,

    determinate interpretations of certain concepts and about the logical (though not

    cultural) arbitrariness of meaning. It is a fundamental hermeneutical issue.11

    Epistemologically, the uncertainty engendered by ambiguity does not rule out

    certainty (say if information improves), because uncertainty itself is deemed to

    be the contingent feature. Much rational choice theory follows that line. But

    indeterminacy rules outdeterminacy. It can offer merely spurious and temporary

    determinacy, engineered (1) by the suspension of disbelief in the possibility of

    determinacy, and (2) by the political awkwardness of belief in the necessity of

    indeterminacy, a belief that could encourage political paralysis.12

    The indeterminacy from which decisionsthose political Ur-actsemanate is

    a structural corollary of the notion of essential contestability, a notion that also

    underpins pluralism. Decisions create the illusionoften through style, rhetoric

    or self-persuasionthat indeterminacy does not exist. Given indeterminacy,

    decisions are closures that permit policies to be formulated or justified against

    a multiple path background. If we accept that position, we will regard thepolitical thinking occurring in a political community as an explicit or implicit

    118 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    10W. Empson, Seven Types of Ambiguity (London: Pimlico, 2004), p. 1.11Cp. T. Bahti, Ambiguity and indeterminacy: the juncture, Comparative Literature, 38 (1986),

    20923.12On this specific point see Freeden, Essential contestability and effective contestability.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    7/22

    competition over the control of political language, and will identify that area as

    the characteristic domain of ideologies. That control is attempted through the

    most necessary feature of the ideological act: the decontestation of the essentially

    contestable, through which a decision is both made possible (accorded an aura

    of finiteness) and justified (accorded an aura of authority). Within the internal

    logic of politics that is both a heuristic necessity and a practical one, as decisions

    must be taken and they then need to be either legitimated or enforced. The

    control over language is an endeavour to monopolize the meanings concepts

    carry. Legitimation and coercion are two methods of establishing monopolies of

    meaning, however fleeting they may be. That controlthat ideological act of

    assertive selectionis a basic feature ofpoliticalthinking.

    Decontestation, though central to political argument, is never conclusive. Here

    we add inconclusiveness to ambiguity and indeterminacy as attributes of politicalconcepts. Inconclusiveness relates to the point where competing appraisals

    of arguments or of policies cannot knock each other out and no further

    improvement can be made on that situation. It relates to the persuasive or

    emotional strength of different claims made by various assertions, whether or

    not through the assembling of evidence. It is a failure of assessment and of

    weighting; not, as with ambiguity, of the clarification of definitional meaning.

    But there is another sense of inconclusivelacking a conclusion. It is also tied

    to the impossibility of reaching an end point in an argumentative chain or string.Say I am an egalitarian who favours greater equalization of wealth, from which

    I deduce a scheme of public transfers such as graduated taxation, and then have

    to consider whether to permit voluntary transfers from one member of a family

    to another, and then ask whether the use of such transfers should be controlled

    in terms of the goods they purchase, all down to the case of whether Mrs.

    Appleton of Hyacinth Avenue, Bolton, a widowed ex-terrorist awaiting a hip

    replacement, whose neighbour is playing very loud music on Saturday nights

    when she wants to sleep, is a disadvantaged individual who requires occasional

    compensation from a cash-strapped municipality, even though in the not-distant

    future she will inherit a large sum of money from her aged uncle, etc. There

    comes a point where, due to argumentative overload, to the inability to

    conceptualize, to the inefficiency of policy-producing results, or to sheer

    boredom, such a chain needs to be stopped (or, more likely, it peters out) even

    though it can still produce endless variations. Those stoppage points may be

    conditioned by moral paradigms, by conventions of argument, by demands of

    efficacy, or by other cultural practices. Here the sequence and detailed path of

    an argument, rather than the internal components of its parts, are curtailed bycomplexity and the limited resources of mental and emotional energy in the face

    of infinity!

    Now, political philosophers may perceive many acts of decontestation as

    examples of poor thinking that, consequently, do not merit serious scholarly

    examination. As I have argued elsewhere, the concept of decontestation muddies

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 119

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    8/22

    the waters of logical imperatives beloved by philosophers by introducing cultural

    constraints on the logical options contained in an argument. Cultural constraints

    are inevitable in a system of thinking when the path-structure of logical trees

    invariably offers a number of entailed solutions, the choice among which would

    otherwise be arbitrary.13 The very arbitrariness of the logical choices as to which

    path to follow is a sharp reminder that logic is the coat hanger, not the coat,

    and that philosophical obsession with logic alone will actually result in

    substantive indeterminacy unless cultural constraints are factored in.

    However, there is another argument political philosophers could bring against

    decontestations. When effected by non-expertsi.e. non-philosophersthey

    may be taken sloppily, and with insufficient justification. That is often true, but

    it is not a good reason for ignoring them. First, the study of political thought

    (and here one finds common ground with historians of political thought) mustleave room for theorizing about the bad and the inadequate side by side with

    the good or the ideal. That is standard practice among political comparativists,

    for example. This point was captured almost a century ago by Graham Wallas,

    in response to James Bryce. Bryce had written about the ideal democracy in

    which every citizen is intelligent, patriotic, disinterested, seeking the right side

    in each contested issue by using his common sense. What, riposted Wallasin

    language as pertinent today as it was thendid Bryce mean by common sense?

    If it means anything it means the best form of democracy which is consistent withthe facts of human nature. But one feels, on reading the whole passage, that Mr.Bryce means by these words the kind of democracy which might be possible ifhuman nature were as he himself would like it to be, and as he was taught at Oxfordto think that it was. If so, the passage is a good instance of the effect of ourtraditional course of study in politics. No doctor would now begin a medicaltreatise by saying, the ideal man requires no food, and is impervious to the actionof bacteria, but this ideal is far removed from the actualities of any knownpopulation.14

    Second, if politics is centrally about decision-making for collectivities, the

    political theorist needs to theorize about the kind of thinking that goes into the

    act of decontestation. Decontestative thinking, and its study, themselves become

    central topoliticaltheory. They have to do different work for us in our capacity

    as political theorists of politics than in our capacity as political philosophers. We

    thus need to investigate the methods, arguments, presentations and devices that

    enable successful decontestation in the political arena. The argument here is

    loosely parallel to that directed against vulgar Marxist views of ideology, views

    that summarily dismissed ideology as distorted consciousness instead ofexploring those forms of distortion and why they mattered, not only to those

    120 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    13See M Freeden, A Very Short Introduction to Ideology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003),pp. 5760.

    14G. Wallas, Human Nature in Politics (London: Constable, 1948; originally published 1908),pp. 1267.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    9/22

    who thought them, but also to those who studied ideology. Whether or not we

    like what we find, as students of society we need to know.

    Two forms of decontestation are well-known, even if not analysed as

    decontestations. The one is the attempt to attach very precise allocations of

    meanings to indeterminate concepts. Characteristic are the carefully-argued

    conceptual clarifications, occasionally definition-constructing, that political

    philosophers attempt as thought-exercises for the recommended handling

    of concepts and arguments. Even here these are predicated on the acts of

    manipulating, limiting, ranking and excluding fields of meaning so as to optimize

    clarity, acts that themselves are of course saliently political. The second is the

    stipulative ascription of meaning to a term, often associated with ideologues (in

    extreme cases totalitarian, caricatured in Orwells 1984 slogans war is peace;

    freedom is slavery; ignorance is strength; but in fact common to all ideologists,as in equality can only be understood as equality of opportunity). This second

    form of decontestation may be underpinned by rhetoric, by invoking extra-

    human sanctification, or by force. Typically, the closure attempted here is

    buttressed by the conclusive manner in which meaning is attached to the

    contested term, accompanied by sleight of mouth, by the harnessing of science,

    God, nature, personal vision, or by threats. One reason for this perceived and

    intended conceptual confidence lies in the nature of authoritativeness, a property

    that political systems need to generate with respect to their elites and prospectivepower-wielders, if those elites are to compete successfully over the control

    of political language. In effect, the two forms of decontestation are not

    dichotomous but represent two points on a continuum, and the distance between

    philosophers and ideologues is not as great as some scholars would have it.

    Stipulative ascription, frequently supported by an appeal to reason, is well within

    the domain of the political theorist and philosopher (justice is the first virtue of

    a society), and the elusive end of authoritativeness is no less sought by scholars

    of political thought when promoting their own theories.

    But the closure of debate does not necessarily ensue from the accuracy of the

    conceptual definition or argumentative solution, or solely from the marketing of

    dominant meanings. There exists a third and equally significant form of closure.

    It could be called simulated decontestation, in which the semblance of

    decontestation is created by ambiguity and by vagueness. Political philosophers

    often label the kinds of political thinking emanating from non-professional

    thinkers, say politicians and the disseminators of popular ideologiesas elusive,

    if not duplicitous. That is, for instance, an accusation levelled at the phrase the

    third way and, from the viewpoint of analytical purists, it is a justified one.Ambiguity in that case relates, for instance, to the lack of clarity concerning the

    first and second waysboth in terms of their substance (e.g., capitalism versus

    communism? Free-market versus welfare state?), and in terms of the location of

    thirdon a continuum defined by first and second, that is to say middle; or

    a Hegelian synthesis of first and second; or outside that frame: an ordinal

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 121

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    10/22

    number distinguished simply by its location on a temporal sequence? Ambiguity

    is, however, also a form of handling political language that is vital to the central

    political aim of mobilizing support. The generation of support is, in terms of

    political theory, significantly dependent on linguistic formulations that are open-

    ended, that carry multiple meanings, and that can be consumed differentially.

    That also connects to the rather different category ofvagueness, pertaining to

    the boundary problems of concepts (to their intension) and to movement across

    categories. Are both communism and the welfare state, for the purposes of a

    specific political argument, simply two instances of excessive state control? Is the

    free-market a sub-set of capitalism or can it be detached from the latter and

    reattached to forms of democratic socialism? And does that then begin to vitiate

    the distinction between capitalism and democratic socialism, or are we looking

    instead at a plethora of ideological configurations as characteristic of real worldpolitical discourse, many of which shade off into others? The blurring of

    boundaries of meaning is often inescapable, but it may also be intentional.

    Controlled and delimited indeterminacy is a typical and indispensable aspect of

    political thinking among decision-making elites, especially if in a particular

    instance the requirement to generate support overrides the requirement for

    authoritative semantic pronouncements. Decision-making may generate support

    from admirers of decisiveness, but it is also a loss-maker in terms of the

    ideational groups it alienates. Accuracy of language (to the extent that it ispossible) is an advantage only if precision is needed to corner a particular

    market of ideological support. Whereas ideological specialization should

    produce strong decontestation, it also entails a limiting of ambition with regard

    to potential support or, alternatively, a reliance on coercion.

    The point is that both ambiguous and vague expressions of political thinking

    cannot just be dismissed as inferior thought-products. If they are, we miss out

    as interpreters of the domain of the politicalon identifying major political

    phenomena and impoverish our understanding of the variety and subtlety of

    political thinking at the disposal of a society. They are, rather, frequently

    intentional and importantly functional forms of political thought. And although

    the general public may see them as confirmation of the bad name given to

    politics, their elusiveness is not simply dissimulation, trickery or slack thinking

    though it may be any of thesebut often the deliberate harnessing of political

    language in order to achieve one of the main ends of politics, quite apart from

    being an existential feature of political language.

    From the perspective of analyzing political thought, the indeterminacy of

    political concepts associated with further properties such as ambiguity (whichmay allow for answers through disambiguation) and vagueness (which cannot

    generate specific answers)15 marks out the inevitable tension between the desire

    122 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    15R. Sorensen, Vagueness and Contradiction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), pp. 23,112.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    11/22

    for decontestation and its impossibility, due to the surplus of meaning any act

    of linguistic closure carries. Even strong decontestation (The only freedom

    which deserves the name, is that of pursuing our own good in our own way16)

    cannot endow political language with precision, and will be open to many

    interpretations, unanticipated as well as anticipated. Particularly for ideologies,

    competing as they do over political power in societies, certainty as well as

    elusiveness are two required features, and fundamental to the political process.

    Both are preliminaries to producing decisions. Liberal polities, especially, are

    positioned between the need of politicians to deliver confidence-generating

    results, and the requirement of liberal ideologies to be flexible in reassessing the

    meanings and applications of polysemic political vocabulary, as well as to

    mobilize the pluralist support believed to be structurally distinctive of modern,

    multiple-identity societies. Sometimes certainty can pay, if a very specific policyis in the making; and the rhetoric and style of certainty are themselves the

    wielding of political power. At other times, and more typically, elusiveness of

    meaning is the key to generating consent.

    Lets put this slightly differently, in the context of recent attempts by political

    philosophers to attain overlapping consensus and undistorted communication in

    a society. Devices to attain consensus, whether of the Rawlsian thin type or the

    Habermasian thicker type, are proffered by those philosophers as a solution to

    the existence of political disagreement, or as the framework within which onlyreasonable disagreement can persist and be controlled. Perfect harmony may be

    posited through utopian thought experiments, and overlapping consensus

    through an appeal to free-standing shared intuitions and moral capacities. But

    politics, we might argue, based on past and present observation, is the site of

    durable dissent as a structural inevitability. Articulatory and augmentative

    precision therefore exacerbate the destructive potential of dissent, as positions

    are sharply marked out not only methodologically but substantively. Here I offer

    one evaluative standpoint from a disciplinary perspective habitually accused of

    eschewing normative evaluation in favour of interpretation andusually

    employed in a derogatory mannerdescription. Vagueness and ambiguity are

    not only the inevitable by-product of indeterminacy, but a recipe for political co-

    existence. The much-vaunted 1950s consensus on the post WW2 welfare state

    in the UK was the product of such ambiguity. It allowed for co-operation

    between very diverse ideological frameworks with the concomitant political

    stability this engendered. It did that through playing down the different

    ideological ends welfare measures serviced: political order and economic

    productivity for the Conservatives, social justice and greater social solidarity forLabour. Imprecision and the elision of meaning are advantageous and desirable,

    when different priorities among political values would otherwise lead to strife.

    The tolerance of words in containing multiple, connected but not identical

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 123

    16J. S. Mill, On Liberty (London: Dent, 1910), p. 75.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    12/22

    meanings, is important to the adequate functioning of political and ideological

    orders. The precision so highly sought by some philosophers may signal the kiss

    of death for political processes.

    IV. STRUCTURAL PLURALISMS AND

    CONCEPTUAL INTERDEPENDENCIES

    So far, the word ideology has crept into this article, but not predominantly

    so. In effect, the political theory of politics is closely related to the study

    of ideologies, but I am very conscious of the contrary and contradictory

    associations of the concept of ideology. The approach advocated here regards

    ideologies as synonymous with the political thinking actually occurring in a

    society, inasmuch as the product is identifiable in patterns (or morphologicalarrangements) and is produced and consumed by politically significant

    collectivities. That is not to suggest that the meaning of ideology can now be

    stretched to take over as the preponderant object of political theory, but rather

    that political theory must avail itself of the methods and techniques that recent

    analyses of ideology have developed, in order to gain access to the vast realm of

    concrete and politically relevant thinking that exists at the heart of the political.

    It also suggests, as noted above, that we almost always encounter political

    thought in the form of ideological discourses.What, then, are the understandings and devices we need to bring into play

    if we wish to do justice as political theorists to this under-researched and

    underconceptualized area? First, if it makes sense to regard the conceptas the

    basic semantic unit of political thinking, political theory needs to investigate the

    presentation, interrelationships and internal structure of its concepts. While

    competition over the control of language should remain pivotal to political

    theory, its emphasis should lie in the analysis of the productthe configurations

    of concepts that constitute a political idea and, at more general levels, an instance

    of political discourse, or an ideology. Second, and I shall return to this below,

    given indeterminacy, ambiguity, vagueness, and inconclusiveness as fundamental

    to political argument and its conceptual components, political theory needs to

    explore the characteristics that these attributes bestow on the political process.

    How do they structure political discourse? How should that knowledge of the

    nature of political language shape our understanding of the political and of

    political thinking?

    Importantly, this genre of political theory must be sensitive to change, as it is

    predicated on the impermanence of conceptual content, and is sensitive to thefluctuating interchange of conceptual structures with the world of practices,

    embracing Skinners observation that acts are also texts.17 But it is not centrally

    124 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    17Q. Skinner, The rise of, challenge to, and prospects for a Collingwoodian approach to thehistory of political thought, The History of Political Thought in National Context, ed. Castiglioneand Hampsher-Monk, p. 186.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    13/22

    concerned with the reasons or conditions for change as with its manifestations

    and consequencesthe varied conceptions of key concepts that come together

    to form patterned yet plastic theories and understandings. Its epistemological

    underpinning in indeterminacy does not signify a flaw in our conception of the

    world or a temporary stage en route to truth and knowledge, but singles out

    the very locus of human choice (and hence conceptual flexibility) itself.

    Indeterminacy is not synonymous with chaos or with extreme relativism, but it

    holds out the promise of infinitely rich combinations of ideas from which

    societies may draw. Methodologically, it underpins the pluralism that guarantees

    that neither political theory nor ideology will ever die out. It is also far more in

    tune with the view of human nature that recent welfare theory has identified

    not one based on a nineteenth century belief in the certainties proffered by

    human reason and in the forcefulness of practical entrepreneurship, but basedon an awareness of human frailty and vulnerability, and hence normally

    susceptible to unpredictable as well as planned change.18 Does building on the

    existence of pluralism signify that political theory can only deal with liberal

    premises and frameworks? Not at all, as the pluralism that is the result of

    essential contestability is a necessary but not sufficient condition of liberalism,

    and because political theorists have to entertain the assumption that the

    ostensible absence of more than one voice, in any ideological system, is achieved

    not through utopian reasonableness and harmony but only through force ormanipulation.

    Another feature of structural pluralism directs us to a further insight germane

    to the political theory of politics. Politics focuses, among others, on the study of

    interrelated individuals and groups, recently rephrased through terms such as

    networks.19 That existential interdependence is matched by the conceptual

    interdependence evident in the thought products of political thinkers. In the real

    world of texts and utterancesas any linguist knowswords come in

    combinations, and so it is with concepts. Despite the proclivity of analytical

    philosophers to explore concepts in isolationa necessary exercise when the

    tolerance and range of a concept is, quite reasonably, subjected to logical and

    argumentative testingconcepts always appear in clusters that are mutually

    defining, sustaining and, for that matter, constraining. Those patterns

    are established through empirical evidence, mediated via the interpretative

    facilities of the researcher, but superimposed on a spinal conceptual structure

    that reveals the options available to political thinkers in a given time and space

    frame.

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 125

    18See M. Freeden, The coming of the welfare state, The Cambridge History of Twentieth CenturyPolitical Thought, ed. T. Ball and R. Bellamy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003),pp. 744.

    19See, e.g., R.A.W. Rhodes, Understanding Governance: Policy, Networks, Governance,Reflexivity and Accountability (Buckingham: Open University Press, 1997); Martin A. Hajer andHendrik Wagenaar, eds, Deliberative Policy Analysis: Understanding Governance in the NetworkSociety (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    14/22

    Take Mills On Liberty, an essay that is not on liberty alone, not even on

    liberty as a super-value. As Mill makes abundantly clear, he is arguing for the

    free development of individualitya cluster of concepts that elicit out of

    each other specific conceptions and that form a particular cultural package

    chosen from a number of logical possibilities.20 Thus, the conception of liberty

    is one that contributes to the development of individuals; other conceptions of

    liberty are structurally ruled out by the proximity engineered to the adjacent

    concepts; while the conception of development is made to include self-

    development, as development not undertaken by free individuals is excluded.21

    We thus encounter a virtuous circle, an instance of complex holistic relationships,

    bearing three features. First, any concept is a means to any other (the circle may

    be entered into at any point on the conceptual compass). Second, some

    conceptions of any concept may also intersect with, or constitute, part of anotherconcept: here complex boundary problems emerge. Thirda normative

    apparelthe configuration of concepts has been constructed so as to constitute

    collectively a desirable, or attractive, set of human and social circumstances.22

    Those are typical ways in which political language and thinking present

    themselves.

    Interdependence, applied to the political world, is not tantamount to an all-

    embracing wholeness. In a world of conflicting and competing conceptual

    arrangements, it appears as competing holisms. One salient shape thesecompeting holisms adopt is that of ideologies, which are now to be viewed as

    all the concrete forms of political thinking in a society that feature either some

    grand conceptual configuration or, more modestly, a partial one. For each

    ideology offers a prevailing pattern of the conceptions of many concepts, bound

    together as a particular discourse. Such holisms are of course not really complete,

    for two reasons. First, the issue of inconclusiveness noted above: arguments

    have no clear endpoints. Second, in a holistic structure ideas and policies are

    interconnected at many points and on many dimensions. Those nodal linkages

    reflect cultural understandings of how and why these connections are, and should

    be, made. But no holistic political structure can host all possible linkages and

    paths. The interdependence of any given cluster of political thought lies rather

    in its particular choice, or presentation, of certain sequential conceptual paths

    and in some configuration of mutually-sustaining circularity. Disparate nodal

    linkages vie with each other in giving different holistic readings (i.e. alternative

    ideological interpretations) of the political practices that are being signified.

    To recapitulate, the sphere of politics is a major arena in which collective

    enterprises take place, and ideologies most typically represent the political

    126 MICHAEL FREEDEN

    20Mill, On Liberty, p. 115.21I have argued this in greater detail in Ideologies and Political Theory, pp. 1457.22These possibilities do not exhaust Mills text. The umbrella concept of well-being actson this

    interpretationas a collective name for the cluster of named goods, but may also, as Mill implies,contain further goods, or further leading essentials.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    15/22

    thought equivalents of these collective ventures. They are both collectively

    produced, and designed to be consumed, by collectivities. Hence any political

    theory aiming at understanding this aspect of the political cannot overlook the

    fundamental claim that the study of ideologies offers the most immediate and

    relevant access to the clustered political thinking of collectivities.

    V. THE ATTRIBUTES OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS AND

    THE SHAPE OF POLITICAL DISCOURSE

    Once we are prepared to forgo the presupposition that collectivities ought to act

    in unison, or that they can leave their differences at the hermetically sealed gate

    of politics, our focus necessarily readjusts to what happens inside the space

    occupied by such collectivities and the sub-groups inside them. Here we mayborrow an idea from institutional analysts: the notion of multi-level governance.

    Comparative political scientists have largely abandoned the unitary assumptions

    about the relationship between politics and the state, and students of political

    thought need to do the same. Multi-level governance assumes that political

    systems harbour variable origins of decision-making. That raises the immediate

    problem of co-ordination. The reflection of that structural requirement is

    negotiationone mechanism for the regulation of any conflict that may emerge.

    The centrality of negotiation to the study of political thought commences withthe pluralism and dissent generated by conceptual indeterminacy, and follows

    them through the political requirement to make decisions. The focal area of the

    political theory of politics lies thus not in the sphere that Rawls called political

    liberalism, but expressly in the spheres of comprehensive doctrines that Rawls

    banished from politics. One of the cores of the politicaldissent and its

    attempted regulation through negotiationis sited in the relationship between

    these so-called comprehensive doctrines.

    Negotiation and compromise are political activities that can prevent the

    eruption of uncontrollable disorder. The fluid structure of political concepts itself

    holds the potential for negotiation, though not all features of political thinking

    for instance, oversimplification or excessive competitive zealare amenable to

    such compromise. Nor can we rule out the many instances of zero-sum

    relationships among core values, against which Rawlsian-type enterprises are

    helpless. Pro-choicers and pro-lifers with regard to the deliberate termination

    of pregnancies constitute one such case, and ambiguityor coercionmay be

    the only way out. Most political theories and ideologies possess non-negotiable

    componentsred lines they will never cross.As an aspect of political thought, negotiation normally accompanies

    decontestation. Negotiation can occur with regard to past conversations within

    a particular political discourse, or between political discourses. The decontested

    forms in which we encounter political concepts do not descend from a conceptual

    heaven but are the product of complex historical and political processes, of

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 127

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    16/22

    inching ones way towards positions that are the result of many adaptive

    conversations. They eventually reach the point where negotiation temporarily

    stops, due to the exigencies of decision-making, or the tolerance and endurance

    levels of the ideological producers. That process is parallel to imposing an

    ephemeral conclusion on inconclusiveness, and it helps us to understand why

    decisions are, from the point of view of political thinking, quasi-arbitrary and

    temporary stoppage points in potentially interminable sequences, and why,

    therefore, a decision is an act of rerouting rather than one of permanently

    halting.

    Equipped with the attributes of political concepts, and taking on board the

    crucial art of political negotiation, how might they be translated into the terms

    of political discourse? As political theorists we need to explore the impact of

    conceptual features, and the leeway of conceptual interpretation possible in aconceptual arrangement, before it begins to affect core positions critically.

    Assume, for example, that we are assessing two policies concerning traffic

    congestion. Behind them lies a general conception of the public interest involving

    physical mobility and the quality of urban life. For some, that public interest

    entails the reduction of pollution in the service of sustainable life on the planet

    (cars are a public bad). For others, it involves an efficient and consumer-oriented

    lifestyle necessitating speed of access to places of work, shopping and

    entertainment. This group could be further divided into those who wish to buildadditional access roads for private vehicles (cars are a public good because they

    advance social mobility and accessibility; rather than a private good because they

    advance individual desires) and those who wish to prioritize public transport

    (buses are a public rather than private good for the same reasons). For others

    again, non-intervention in private choices is the relevant conception of the public

    interest (this is not identical to the aggregate of private interests but a competing

    evaluation of the good life) and congestion is one of the prices we pay for a free

    society (the goodness or badness of cars is irrelevant, and the quality of urban

    life is a consequence of the free choices available to residents). Already, the

    political terrain is constructed on the indeterminacy of the public good and of

    the relative weighting of its components, and the vagueness of the boundary

    relationship between private and public transport (say, between a privately hired

    school bus and a school bus operated by a private company under licence of the

    local authority).

    The town, however, is clogged up and for most people that cost is too high.

    Can the different conceptions of the good life allow a solution? The municipality

    decides to assess two options, taking into account the prevalence of thosedifferent beliefs concerning the good life and the inevitability of dissent on

    those matters. The one proposal is to forgo regulation and to anticipate that

    congestion will make travel so unattractive that individuals will find it easier to

    leave their cars at home rather than face gridlock. The other is to impose a

    128 MICHAEL FREEDEN

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    17/22

    congestion charge. In decoding these perimeter practices23 we must first try to

    set them within the ideological environment that best makes sense of them. The

    two options offer at least three possible strategies of argument for the rationing

    of public road space. The first sees self-rationing as an inevitable consequence

    of excessive private demand for geographical mobility, and when individuals

    are penalized by gridlock it relies on private, rational choices. As a market

    mechanism it is self-regulatory: motorists will despair and vote with their wheels;

    those who nevertheless insist on driving in city centres will pay the price in time

    and nerves. The second justifies centralized rationing by invoking environmental

    concerns to trump individual choice, and imposes regulations irrespective of

    democratic soundingsfor example, the opening of space only to public

    transport. The third invokes efficiency of movement in terms of time and space.

    However, as happened in London, it combines market practicesleasing publicspaceand a regressive tax that penalizes the worse-off while still enabling

    the wealthy to swan around town centre, with an alternative concern for

    redistributive justice: namely, the proceeds of the congestion charge are

    channelled to a considerable extent towards subsidising public transport.

    The attractiveness of this solutionfor those to whom it may be attractive in

    the first placeis that it relies on the ambiguity of the conception of the public

    good it is intended to satisfy. Whose interests is it serving? Whose view of the

    good life can it claim to benefit? It is not a case of zero-sum ambiguity, whereone interpretation may rule out the other (e.g. the desirability of experimenting

    on animals) but of compatible ambiguity, utilizing the possibility that all parties

    maywith some tweakingread their preferred, or at least an acceptable,

    position into the proffered solution. In effect, it illustrates a struggle over a

    particular cashing out of the public interest, stretched indeterminately between

    three positions: 1. The predominance of private interests, and freedom from the

    nuisance of physical intervention by others in my relatively efficient free

    movement through town (assisted by an ability to pay that itself is a product ofmarket forces). 2. The objective interest of human and extra-human entities,

    underpinned by a scientific, expert and non-democratic decontestation of

    (environmental) values. 3. The postulation of a communal, electorally popular,

    interest best served within current cultural constraints by charging for free

    choice, and addressing the consequent inequality of opportunity for movement

    by compensating those unable to avail themselves of it. If conceptual flexibility

    allows for a sustainable overlapping area to elide ideological differences and to

    reach a policy-decision, then negotiation over the content of political concepts

    is possible and may result in a compromiseeach side can go back to its

    supporters and claim reasonable success. Political consensus, to repeat, is

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 129

    23For an explanation of perimeter practices see Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory,pp. 7880.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    18/22

    predicated on ambiguity, not precision, and as political theorists we must

    understand both how the construction of ambiguity works, and how to produce

    it when necessary.

    Nevertheless, unanticipated strains in that coalition of conceptions may cause

    it to unravel at any future point, or to react violently back on the stability of

    conceptual cores. Decontestation is itself subject to continuous reformulation

    over time and space. Essential contestability engenders slippage as a consequence

    of the internal flexibility of positions and the impossibility (and political

    undesirability) of holding linguistic meaning constant. There always exists a

    decontestation continuum, in which subtle reformulations (negotiated or

    unprompted) are marshalled in order to remain in the competition over the

    control of political language. That is where inconclusiveness emerges, for the

    imposition of a congestion charge will effectively be, as argued above, anunavoidably temporary decision. The solution may have to be extended in future,

    it may be abolished as electorally unsustainable, or its success may create other

    harms that have to be addressed.

    VI. RANKING AND THE DISTRIBUTION OF SIGNIFICANCE

    There is at least one further vital feature of political discourse that assists in

    engendering support and enabling political decisions. If politics still is, in HaroldLasswells famous phrase, about who gets what, when, how then its discursive

    equivalent in political theory is the distribution of significance to open fields of

    meaning: endowing this meaning of a concept, of an argument, of a practice

    with greater significance than thatmeaning. At the heart of politics are acts of

    ranking, of expressing preferences, of establishing a pecking order of importance,

    in a world where there are finite material, intellectual and emotional resources

    that can be called on to construct, or support, or justify policy. That ranking is

    a prerequisite of political decision-making, without which decision-makers

    cannot know what to deal with next. Ranking attempts to transform the

    essentially indeterminate weighting and sequencing of priority claims into a

    determinate one. Unlike the notion of hierarchy, it does not necessarily denote

    a durable institutional structure, nor the bestowal of superior consideration on

    people and offices, but rather a process central to political judgment, assessment

    and choice.

    How does political thought handle this issue? Notably, some political concepts

    and some forms of political language are primarily dedicated to ranking. To

    illustrate, we need to reconsider a well-known concept in political theory fromapolitical, not ethical, perspective. A right, from that viewpoint, is a linguistic

    device that discharges the function of cruciallyprioritizingandprotectingvalues

    and desired objects. It is a concept that shoots other valued concepts to the

    top of the queue and accords them greater weight and durabilityi.e. it

    (re)distributes their significance. Rights are always a protective capsule for other

    130 MICHAEL FREEDEN

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    19/22

    valuesrights are not substantive values themselvesand that very act of

    linguistic protection and ring-fencing is a pristine political act. Rights regulate

    conflict through attempted demarcations of boundaries of human action and

    expectation. The very language of rights endeavours to render those boundaries

    impermeable, through adjectival contrivances such as natural or inalienable,24

    and that is a major form of coping with essential contestability. Rights are often

    accompanied by the concepts of legitimacy and authority. These mobilize

    political support through manufacturing consent and obediencetwo

    indispensable political goods, irrespective of any ethical worth they may carry,

    that confer durability on ranking. All these concepts embody the conceptual

    polysemy and indeterminacy that necessitate ranking exercises in order for

    political activity to be possible.

    Ranking is also abetted by persuasivenessan aspect of (political) powerpertaining to the assembling of cogent, effective, or attractive arrangements of

    political concepts and conceptions incorporated in political argument. Here the

    focus is on utilizing the cultural tools that are best geared to changing peoples

    opinions or to securing them: rational argument, an appeal to the past, the

    summoning up of Gods will, or nationalist fervour are some of the options. That

    too is a major consideration in constructing a political theory of politics, because

    it examines which devices aid one argument to gain salience over another.

    VII. REFLECTIONS ON THE ROLE OF POLITICAL THEORISTS

    Ethicists might have a point when they ask: How does this kind of political

    analysis further the goals of providing a critique of existing practices and

    principles, and of prescribing better ones? Simply to argue that the political

    theory of politics focuses on different aspects of politics is only partially correct.

    Nor is it quite enough to claim that morality is no more than an attractive way

    through which to shape legitimacy discourses, and that morality tests are weighty

    tests of the actions of governments and the ends of regimes. That assigns morality

    an instrumental value. The greater challenge is to demonstrate that the political

    theory of politics can provide tools to ethico-political philosophers

    (conventionally referred to as normative philosophers). True, if we assume that

    individuals as a rule appreciate good or moral reasons for acting, then legitimacy

    claims and understandings have to be couched in moral terms. But as analysts

    of political language and concepts we will want to know which conceptions of

    which concepts generate and enable arguments about the intrinsic good

    of political morality. We need to know how political visions are constructed.Does a cocktail of transparency, pluralism and legitimacy offer the winning

    combination? Or one of loyalty, nationhood and sacrifice? Which conceptions

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 131

    24I initially developed that approach to rights in M. Freeden, Rights (Buckingham: OpenUniversity Press, 1991).

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    20/22

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    21/22

    theorizing that employs conceptual analyses and interpretative tools pertaining

    to political ideas and language, and that should stem directly from our training

    aspoliticaltheorists. Not the least of the benefits might be that political theorists

    and political scientists start talking to each other again.

    It is not the past abstractness of political theory that is at fault (as Smith

    agrees26) but its extreme reluctance to enter the muddied waters of regular

    political discourse on the one hand, and to illuminate the kinds of core political

    issues that political theorists have heavily underplayed on the other hand. It is

    not the lack of relevance to current political issues that is at stake but the lack

    of relevance to understanding the nature of theorizing and thinking about

    politics, an enterprise that has largely been abandoned by political theorists, but

    that has been resurrected and developed by students of ideology. It is not so

    much a question about which events and practices we ought to focus on. Rather,what needs to be rethought is: what should we be doing as political theorists

    engaged in understanding and exploring political phenomena? In order to do

    theoryto analyse and construct new abstractionswhat do we need to know

    about the political thought produced by the members of a society, and what

    should we ask about it?

    Ten years ago I was writing about the gap between political philosophy and

    the history of ideas, and arguing that the study of ideology filled that gap. Now

    I am arguing that the space between theory and practice in political studies needsto be filled not just by a convergence between theory and empirical studies, but

    by developing an approach that fills another gap: between apolitical and

    political, distanced and immediate, theorizingabout politics. That gap, I claim,

    can be filled through acknowledging that generalized political thinkingnamely,

    concrete and ubiquitous forms of discourse and debate that shape and reflect the

    political domain, for better or for worseis a major concern of political theory,

    and then enabling political theory to utilize and develop a vocabulary that will

    translate that concern into scholarship. If we do not pay attention to those

    phenomena, we will overlook a vital aspect of politics and of its incarnation in

    patterns of human thought. Moreover, we shall be deflected from what is

    centrallypoliticalin our thought-patterns. True, we also need to be engaged

    but that is in our role as social ethicists and as citizens. As students of political

    thinking we need to emulate the practices of anthropologistsdonning the

    mantle of conceptologistsin order to map and interpret the strange, wonderful

    and occasionally repulsive world of political ideas on which we all feed and that

    permeates the conscious and unconscious assumptions incorporated in the

    activity of thinking about politics.Put differently, there are two types of engagement: the one is with the

    immediate pressing social, moral and economic issues and movements that

    require addressing by the intellectuals and decision-makers of the daythat is,

    WHAT SHOULD POLITICAL IN POLITICAL THEORY EXPLORE? 133

    26Ibid., p. 75.

  • 7/28/2019 Freeden_ThePoliticalInPoliticalTheory_05

    22/22

    the urgent ethical and psychological imperative of expressing outrage or hope,

    of trying to make a difference in the world. This flirtation with missionary zeal

    has tempted many scholars out of their ivory towers, and so it should be, but

    such virtuous conduct is often acquired through short-term reactions to what

    is politically and ethically fashionable. Ironically, such activities could be

    categorized just as persuasively as ideological rather than as philosophical. The

    other engagement is with the relevance of the approaches and methods that

    political theorists, as scholars, employ in order to shed light on their subject-

    matter, to understand and interpret it. The first is more dramatic and would seem

    to produce more compelling results; but the second is more effective, more

    carefully self-reflexive, more in line with our responsibilities to our profession as

    academics rather than public intellectuals, and it should produce sturdier

    frameworks within which longer-term workable results are possible. One cannotdiscuss real world political issues without having a method that identifies the

    features of real world political thinking.

    There is still a Rubicon to be crossed: How can this approach gain intellectual

    and academic respectability in comparison with the heavy-weight and established

    disciplines of political philosophy and the history of political thought? Well,

    there is no need for competition if the aims and methods of each are clearly

    understood and if, most importantly, the boundaries between them are not

    conceived of as impermeable but may be regularly traversed to mutual benefit.All are eminently important, because they discharge such different yet

    intellectually necessary tasks. But there certainly exists a challenge, one that the

    political theory of politics can only meet by demonstrating the complexity and

    rigour of its analysisfor which it must be indebted to philosophyand the

    interpretative significance of its findings. It will do so through establishing the

    empirical and evidential investigation of political thinking, through developing

    the analytical categories best suited to the tasks in hand, through the meticulous

    insistence on discerning both distinctions and the configurations in which they

    occur, through the micro-analysis of political language as conceptual as well as

    symbolic, through the sensitivity to political practices as containing ideational

    import and to political thinking itself as a social practice, through the recognition

    that intentionality and unintentionality, agency and culture, reason and emotion,

    interact and inform each other mutually in the political sphere, and through the

    incorporation of temporal and spatial flexibilities and shifts as part and parcel

    of the fluid processes of the formation of political meaning.

    134 MICHAEL FREEDEN